REVISED OCTOBER 18,
2001
IN THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
APPEALS
FOR THE FIFTH CIRCUIT
No. 99-10331
UNITED STATES OF
AMERICA,
Plaintiff-Appellant,
versus
TIMOTHY JOE
EMERSON,
Defendant-Appellee.
Appeals from the United States
District Court
for the Northern District of
Texas
October 16,
2001
Before GARWOOD,
DeMOSS and PARKER, Circuit Judges.
GARWOOD, Circuit
Judge:
The United States
appeals the district court’s dismissal of the indictment of Defendant-Appellee
Dr. Timothy Joe Emerson (Emerson) for violating 18 U.S.C. §
922(g)(8)(C)(ii). The district
court held that section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii) was unconstitutional on its face under
the Second Amendment and as applied to Emerson under the Due Process Clause of
the Fifth Amendment. We reverse and
remand.
Facts and
Proceedings Below
On August 28,
1998, Sacha Emerson, Emerson’s wife, filed a petition for divorce in the 119th
District Court of Tom Green County, Texas.
The petition also requested, inter alia, a temporary injunction
enjoining Emerson from engaging in any of twenty-nine enumerated acts. On September 4, 1998, Judge Sutton held
a temporary orders evidentiary hearing.
Sacha Emerson was represented by counsel while Emerson appeared pro
se. There is no evidence that
Emerson was unable (financially or otherwise) to retain counsel for the hearing
or that he desired representation by counsel on that occasion. He announced ready at the beginning of
the September 4 hearing. Almost all
of Sacha Emerson’s direct testimony concerned financial matters, but the
following relevant exchange took place on direct examination by her
attorney:
Q You are here today asking the Court for
temporary orders regarding yourself and your daughter; is that
correct?
A Yes.
Q You have asked in these restraining orders
regarding Mr. Emerson in that he not communicate with you in an obscene, vulgar,
profane, indecent manner, in a coarse or offensive manner?
A Yes.
Q He has previous to today threatened to kill
you; is that correct?
A He hasn’t threatened to kill me. He’s threatened to kill a friend of
mine.
Q Okay. And he has threatened – he has made some
phone calls to you about that?
A Yes.[1]
Emerson declined
an opportunity to cross-examine Sacha and presented no evidence tending to
refute any of her above quoted testimony or to explain his conduct in that
respect. In his testimony he stated
in another connection, among other things, that he was suffering from “anxiety”
and was not “mentally in a good state of mind.”
On September 14,
1998, Judge Sutton issued a temporary order that included a “Temporary
Injunction” which stated that Emerson “is enjoined from” engaging in any of
twenty-two enumerated acts, including the following:
“2. Threatening
Petitioner in person, by telephone, or in writing to take unlawful action
against any person.”
“4.
Intentionally, knowingly, or recklessly causing bodily injury to Petitioner or
to a child of either party.”
“5. Threatening
Petitioner or a child of either party with imminent bodily injury.”
The order
provides that it “shall continue in force until the signing of the final decree
of divorce or until further order of this court.” The September 14, 1998 order did not
include any express finding that Emerson posed a future danger to Sacha or to
his daughter Logan.[2] There is nothing to indicate that
Emerson ever sought to modify or challenge any of the provisions of the
September 14, 1998 order.
On December 8,
1998, the grand jury for the Northern District of Texas, San Angelo division,
returned a five-count indictment against Emerson. The government moved to dismiss counts 2
through 5, which motion the district court subsequently granted.[3] Count 1, the only remaining count and
the count here at issue, alleged that Emerson on November 16, 1998, unlawfully
possessed “in and affecting interstate commerce” a firearm, a Beretta pistol,
while subject to the above mentioned September 14, 1998 order, in violation of
18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(8). It appears
that Emerson had purchased the pistol on October 10, 1997, in San Angelo, Texas,
from a licensed firearms dealer.
Emerson does not claim that the pistol had not previously traveled in
interstate or foreign commerce. It
is not disputed that the September 14, 1998 order was in effect at least through
November 16, 1998.
Emerson moved
pretrial to dismiss the indictment, asserting that section 922(g)(8), facially
and as applied to him, violates the Second Amendment and the Due Process Clause
of the Fifth Amendment. He also
moved to dismiss on the basis that section 922(g)(8) was an improper exertion of
federal power under the Commerce Clause and that, in any case, the law
unconstitutionally usurps powers reserved to the states by the Tenth
Amendment. An evidentiary hearing
was held on Emerson’s motion to dismiss.
The district
court granted Emerson’s motions to dismiss. Subsequently, the district court issued
an amended memorandum opinion reported at 46 F.Supp.2d 598 (N.D. Tex.
1999). The district court held that
dismissal of the indictment was proper on Second or Fifth Amendment grounds, but
rejected Emerson’s Tenth Amendment and Commerce Clause
arguments.
The government
appealed. Emerson filed a notice of
cross-appeal, which was dismissed by this Court. The government challenges the district
court’s dismissal on Second and Fifth Amendment grounds. Emerson defends the district court’s
dismissal on those grounds and also urges that dismissal was in any event proper
under the Commerce Clause and on statutory
grounds.
Discussion
I. Construction of 18
U.S.C. § 922(g)(8)
18 U.S.C. § 922
provides in
relevant part:
“(g) It shall be
unlawful for any person–
....
(8) who is
subject to a court order that–
(A) was issued
after a hearing of which such person received actual notice, and at which such
person had an opportunity to participate;
(B) restrains
such person from harassing, stalking, or threatening an intimate partner of such
person or child of such intimate partner or person, or engaging in other conduct
that would place an intimate partner in reasonable fear of bodily injury to the
partner or child; and
(C)(i) includes a
finding that such person represents a credible threat to the physical safety of
such intimate partner or child; or
(ii) by its terms
explicitly prohibits the use, attempted use, or threatened use of physical force
against such intimate partner or child that would reasonably be expected to
cause bodily injury; or
....
to ship or
transport in interstate or foreign commerce, or possess in or affecting
commerce, any firearm or ammunition; or to receive any firearm or ammunition
which has been shipped or transported in interstate or foreign
commerce.”
Emerson argues
that section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii) should be construed to require that the particular
predicate court order include an explicit finding that the person enjoined posed
a credible threat of violence to his spouse or child. Emerson further argues that the statute
must also be read to require that the predicate order be supported by sufficient
evidence before the court entering it to sustain such a finding, so that the
court in the criminal prosecution must examine the record in the proceeding
before the court entering the predicate order and must acquit the defendant in
the criminal case if the evidence before the court entering the predicate order
was not sufficient to sustain such a finding. It is, of course, our duty to construe a
statute so as to avoid any serious constitutional questions. However, the statute must be susceptible
to that construction, i.e. our construction must be fairly possible; the duty to
avoid constitutional questions is not a license to rewrite the statute. Jones v. United States, 119 S.Ct.
1215, 1222 (1999); Feltner v. Columbia Pictures Television, Inc., 118
S.Ct. 1279, 1283 (1998); United States v. Albertini, 105 S.Ct. 2897, 2902
(1985). “If the statutory language
is unambiguous, in the absence of ‘a clearly expressed legislative intent to the
contrary, that language must ordinarily be regarded as conclusive.’” Russello v. United States, 104
S.Ct. 296, 299 (1983) (quoting United States v. Turkette, 101 S.Ct. 2524,
2527 (1981)). In addition, if
uncertainty remains after an examination of the statute’s text, its legislative
history and the policies it advances, the rule of lenity requires this
uncertainty to be resolved in favor of Emerson. United States v. Prestenbach, 230
F.3d 780, n.23 (5th Cir. 2000).
Turning first to
Emerson’s second statutory argument, there is nothing in the text of the statute
to support it. Moreover, it is
contrary to uniform construction of section 922(g) and its predecessors under
which the courts have construed this and other similar subsections of section
922. See, e.g., Lewis v. United
States, 100 S.Ct. 915 (1980); United States v. Chambers, 922 F.2d
228, 232-40 (5th Cir. 1991). Just
as Lewis observed that “nothing [in the statutory text] suggests any
restriction on the scope of the term ‘convicted,’” id. at 918, so also
nothing in section 922(g)(8) suggests that the validity of the particular
predicate court order may be inquired into in the section 922(g)(8) criminal
prosecution. Moreover, this is
consistent with the long standing federal rule that violation of an injunction
that is subsequently invalidated may, at least so long as it cannot be
characterized as having only a transparent or frivolous pretense to validity, be
punished as criminal contempt.
See Chambers at 239-40; National Maritime Union v. Aquaslide
‘N’ Drive Corp., 737 F.2d 1395, 1399-1400 (5th Cir. 1984).[4]
We likewise
reject the argument that section 922(g)(8) requires that the predicate order
contain an express judicial finding that the defendant poses a credible threat
to the physical safety of his spouse or child. If the requirements of 922(g)(8)(A) and
(B) are fulfilled, then by its terms section 922(g)’s firearms disability
attaches if either clause (C)(i) or clause (C)(ii) applies. Although an express judicial finding of
future dangerousness pursuant to section 922(g)(8)(C)(i) is one way section
922(g)(8)’s firearms disability can attach, to construe section 922(g)(8) as
always requiring an express judicial finding would be to substitute the word
“and” for the word “or” that appears at the end of 922(g)(8)(C)(i). If Congress intended to require an
express judicial finding, it would have arranged the elements as
922(g)(8)(A)-(D) and used the word “and” rather than “or” to join
them.
Notwithstanding
the lack of textual ambiguity, Emerson maintains that we should either imply the
express judicial finding requirement into section 922(g)(8) or at least
recognize the lack of an express judicial finding as an affirmative defense to
section 922(g)(8). He argues that,
without the requirement of an express judicial finding, sections 922(g)(8)(B)
and (C)(ii) are redundant while section 922(g)(8)(A) is rendered a nullity. While there is some overlap between
section 922(g)(8)(B) and (C)(ii), each still has some independent scope in the
statutory scheme. Section 922(g)(8)(B) broadly refers to orders that restrain
harassing, stalking or threatening.
It is quite possible that an order could surmount the section
922(g)(8)(B) hurdle and yet only fulfill one of the section 922(g)(8)(C)
criteria. Congress obviously felt
that if the order only “restrains” harassing, stalking, threatening, or
otherwise causing fear of injury, an express judicial finding of a credible
threat of violence was necessary.
Section 922(g)(8)(B) and (C)(i).
However, if the order “by its terms explicitly prohibits” the use,
attempted use or threatened use of physical force, no such express finding was
necessary. Section
922(g)(8)(C)(ii). Thus, Congress
affirmatively drew a distinction between orders “explicitly prohibiting” the
actual, attempted or threatened physical attack and those merely “restraining”
stalking or harassment. It is true
that both sections embrace orders that proscribe threats, but this degree of
congruence is insufficient to overcome the plain meaning of the text. Nor do we agree that the absence
of a requirement of an express judicial finding renders section 922(g)(8)(A) a
nullity.
Emerson also
argues that the word “restrain”, as used in 922(g)(8)(B), necessarily requires
an express judicial finding that the defendant poses a credible threat of
violence to his spouse or child.
The argument is simply that both temporary and permanent injunctions
traditionally require, in addition to notice and hearing, some express judicial
finding supporting the court’s order.
While this may be generally true, it is not invariably the case that
injunctions must contain such findings and, more importantly, the argument made
does not overcome the fact that Congress specifically required notice and
hearing in all section 922(g)(8) cases but affirmatively and specifically
required an express finding only in cases governed by clause (C)(i). The crux of the matter is that we cannot
imply in clause (C)(ii) an express finding requirement that is not stated in it
while being affirmatively and specifically stated in clause (C)(i).
Relying on the
legislative history of section 922(g)(8), Emerson and amicus the State of
Alabama contend that all three versions of the bill (one from the House, two
from the Senate) that went to the Conference Committee required an express
judicial finding. They contend that
the real purpose of section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii) is to close a “loophole” in section
922(g)(8) that would have prevented it from applying if the express judicial
finding was not in the order itself, but instead, for example, in an
accompanying memorandum. We find
neither argument ultimately persuasive.
Contrary to the assertions of Emerson and the State of Alabama, one of
the Senate versions of the bill that went to the Conference Committee did
authorize a firearms disability without any express judicial finding. This version resulted from amendment
1179 to S.1607, submitted by Senator Biden for Senator Wellstone on November 10,
1993. Amendment 1179 provided, in
relevant part:
“(8)(A) has been
convicted in any court of an offense that-
(i) involves the
use, attempted use, or threatened use of physical force against a person who is
a spouse, former spouse, domestic partner, child, or former child of the person;
or
(ii) by its
nature, involves a substantial risk that physical force against a person who is
a spouse, former spouse, domestic partner, child, or former child of the person
may be used in the course of committing the offense; or
(B) is required,
pursuant to an order issued by any court in a case involving a person described
in subparagraph (A), to refrain from any contact with or to maintain a minimum
distance from that person, or to refrain from abuse, harassment, or stalking of
that person.”
139 Cong. Rec.
S15638-03, *S15650. This language
was sent to the Conference Committee on November 24, 1993, and clearly
contemplates a firearms disability without either a conviction or an express
judicial finding of future dangerousness.
139 Cong. Rec. S17095-03, *S17174.[5] Emerson’s contention that
922(g)(8)(C)(ii)’s presence in the statute cannot be explained by anything sent
to the Conference Committee is unfounded.
Similarly, there is nothing in the legislative history suggesting that
Congress, or any of its committees or members, ever addressed, considered or had
called to its or their attention the supposed “loophole” in the statutory scheme
now put forth by Emerson.
Because the
construction urged by Emerson is not fairly possible, we must decline his
invitation to rewrite section 922(g)(8).
Likewise, because section 922(g)(8) is not ambiguous, the rule of lenity
provides no basis for relief.
II. Due Process Clause of the Fifth
Amendment
The district
court held that prosecution for violating section 922(g)(8) would deprive
Emerson of his Fifth Amendment right to Due Process because: 1) Dr. Emerson did
not know that possession of a firearm while being subject to the September 14,
1998 order was a crime; 2) section 922(g)(8) is an “obscure criminal provision”
that would be difficult for Emerson to discover; 3) there is nothing inherently
evil about possessing a firearm; and 4) Emerson had no reason to suspect that
being subject to the September 14, 1998 order would criminalize otherwise lawful
behavior. United States v.
Emerson, 46 F.Supp.2d 598, 611-13.
The district court relied upon Lambert v. California, 78 S.Ct.
240, 243 (1957), in which the Supreme Court struck down a Los Angeles law
requiring resident felons to register with the city. The Supreme Court observed that: 1) the
defendant had been prosecuted for passive activity; 2) the defendant was unaware
of the need to register; 3) circumstances that would have prompted an inquiry
into the necessity of registration were lacking; and 4) an average member of the
community would not consider the punished conduct blameworthy.
Id.
At the outset, we
note that “[t]he sweep of the Lambert case has been limited by subsequent
decisions of the Supreme Court, lest it swallow the general rule that ignorance
of the law is no excuse.” United
States v. Giles, 640 F.2d 621, 628 (5th Cir. 1981). 18 U.S.C. § 924(a)(2) provides that the
required mens rea for conviction under section 922(g) is knowledge
(“Whoever knowingly violates subsection . . . (g) . . . of section 922 . .
.”). “Knowingly”–in contrast to at
least some uses of “wilfully”–does not require that the defendant know that his
actions are unlawful, but only that he know he is engaging in the activity that
the legislature has proscribed.
Bryan v. United States, 118 S.Ct. 1939, 1945-47 (1998). Bryan explained that Staples
v. United States, 114 S.Ct. 1793 (1994), exemplifies this distinction. In Staples, the Supreme Court
held that conviction for unlawful possession of a machine gun did not require
knowledge that machine gun possession was unlawful, but only knowledge that the
weapon possessed was a machine gun.
Bryan, 118 S.Ct. at 1946 (under Staples “[i]t was not,
however, necessary, to prove that the defendant knew that his possession was
unlawful”). Here, there is no
question that Emerson was aware that on November 16, 1998, he actively possessed
a firearm of the kind covered by the statute while subject to the September 14,
1998 order or that he misapprehended the actual contents of that order.[6]
Moreover, Emerson
filled out and signed BATF Form 4473 when, on October 10, 1997, he purchased the
Beretta semi-automatic pistol referred to in Count 1. This afforded notice to Emerson that so
long as he was under a court order such as that of September 14, 1998, federal
law prohibited his continued possession of that weapon.[7] In Giles, we distinguished
Lambert on this basis (as well as others), noting “Giles’ situation, of
course, is far different from that of Ms. Lambert, for he was directly
confronted with accurate written notice of the conduct proscribed by the statute
[then § 922(h)(1)] when he filled out and signed a Form 4473 as part of each
firearm purchase.” Giles,
640 F.2d at 628. Finally, we agree
with the district court that firearms ownership is not inherently evil or
suspect and that thus a certain mens rea is required. Staples, 114 S.Ct. at
1799-1801. However, Bryan
and Staples make clear that the necessary mens rea in this context
does not require knowledge of the law but merely of the legally relevant
facts. Giles rejects
application of Lambert at least where, as here, there is the notice
provided by the Form 4473. For
these reasons, we hold that Emerson’s case does not merit relief under
Lambert, and that the district court erred when it granted Emerson’s
motion to dismiss the indictment as violating his Fifth Amendment Due Process
rights on that basis.
III. Commerce
Clause
The district
court rejected Emerson’s contention that, in enacting section 922(g)(8),
Congress exceeded its power under the Commerce Clause. As the district court noted, this Court
has held that, because section 922(g)(8) only criminalizes the possession of
firearms or ammunition “in or affecting commerce” and the reception of firearms
that have been “shipped or transported in interstate or foreign commerce”,
Congress did not exceed its Article I, Section 8 powers in enacting it. United States v. Pierson, 139
F.3d 501, 503 (5th Cir.), cert. denied, 119 S.Ct. 220 (1998). Accordingly, the district court, as
bound by this precedent as we are, did not err in denying Emerson’s motion to
dismiss the indictment on Commerce Clause grounds.[8]
IV. Tenth Amendment
The district
court held that congressional enactment of section 922(g)(8) did not violate the
Tenth Amendment to the Constitution.
Finding no reference to this issue in Emerson’s brief to this Court, we
must consider his Tenth Amendment claim abandoned.
V. Second
Amendment
The Second
Amendment provides:
“A well regulated
Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the
people to keep and bear arms, shall not be infringed.”
A. Introduction and Overview of Second Amendment
Models
The district
court held that the Second Amendment recognizes the right of individual citizens
to own and possess firearms, and declared that section 922(g)(8) was
unconstitutional on its face because it requires that a citizen be disarmed
merely because of being subject to a “boilerplate [domestic relations
injunctive] order with no particularized findings.” Emerson, 46 F.Supp.2d at
611. The government opines that
stare decisis requires us to reverse the district court’s embrace of the
individual rights model. Amici for
the government argue that even if binding precedent does not require reversal,
the flaws in the district court’s Second Amendment analysis
do.
In the last few
decades, courts and commentators have offered what may fairly be characterized
as three different basic interpretations of the Second Amendment. The first is that the Second Amendment
does not apply to individuals; rather, it merely recognizes the right of a state
to arm its militia.[9] This “states’ rights” or “collective
rights” interpretation of the Second Amendment has been embraced by several of
our sister circuits.[10] The government commended the states’
rights view of the Second Amendment to the district court, urging that the
Second Amendment does not apply to individual
citizens.
Proponents of the
next model admit that the Second Amendment recognizes some limited species of
individual right. However, this
supposedly “individual” right to bear arms can only be exercised by
members of a functioning, organized state militia who bear the arms while and as
a part of actively participating in the organized militia’s activities. The “individual” right to keep
arms only applies to members of such a militia, and then only if the federal and
state governments fail to provide the firearms necessary for such militia
service. At present, virtually the
only such organized and actively functioning militia is the National Guard, and
this has been the case for many years.
Currently, the federal government provides the necessary implements of
warfare, including firearms, to the National Guard, and this likewise has long
been the case. Thus, under this
model, the Second Amendment poses no obstacle to the wholesale disarmament of
the American people. A number of
our sister circuits have accepted this model, sometimes referred to by
commentators as the sophisticated collective rights model.[11] On appeal the government has abandoned
the states’ rights model and now advocates the sophisticated collective rights
model.
The third model
is simply that the Second Amendment recognizes the right of individuals to keep
and bear arms. This is the view
advanced by Emerson and adopted by the district court. None of our sister circuits has
subscribed to this model, known by commentators as the individual rights model
or the standard model. The
individual rights view has enjoyed considerable academic endorsement, especially
in the last two decades.[12]
We now turn to
the question of whether the district court erred in adopting an individual
rights or standard model as the basis of its construction of the Second
Amendment.
B. Stare Decisis and United States v.
Miller
The government
steadfastly maintains that the Supreme Court’s decision in United States v.
Miller, 59 S.Ct. 816 (1939), mandated acceptance of the collective rights or
sophisticated collective rights model, and rejection of the individual rights or
standard model, as a basis for construction of the Second Amendment. We
disagree.
Only in United
States v. Miller has the Supreme Court rendered any holding respecting the
Second Amendment as applied to the federal government.[13] There, the indictment charged the
defendants with transporting in interstate commerce, from Oklahoma to Arkansas,
an unregistered “Stevens shotgun having a barrel less than 18 inches in length”
without having the required stamped written order, contrary to the National
Firearms Act.[14] The defendants filed a demurrer
challenging the facial validity of the indictment on the ground that “[t]he
National Firearms Act . . . offends the inhibition of the Second Amendment,” and
“[t]he District Court held that section 11 of the Act [proscribing interstate
transportation of a firearm, as therein defined, that lacked registration or a
stamped order] violates the Second Amendment. It accordingly sustained the demurrer
and quashed the indictment.”
Id. at 817-18. The
government appealed, and we have examined a copy of its brief.[15] The Miller defendants neither
filed any brief nor made any appearance in the Supreme Court.
The government’s
Supreme Court brief “[p]reliminarily” points out that:
“. . . the
National Firearms Act does not apply to all firearms but only to a limited class
of firearms. The term ‘firearm’ is
defined in Section 1 of the Act. . . to refer only to ‘a shotgun or rifle having
a barrel of less than 18 inches in length, or any other weapon, except a pistol
or revolver, from which a shot is discharged by an explosive if such weapon is
capable of being concealed on the person, or a machine gun, and includes a
muffler or silencer for any firearm whether or not such firearm is included
within the foregoing definition.’” (id. at
6).
In this
connection the brief goes on to assert that it is “indisputable that Congress
was striking not at weapons intended for legitimate use but at weapons which
form the arsenal of the gangster and the desperado” (id. at 7) and that
the National Firearms Act restricts interstate transportation “of only those
weapons which are the tools of the criminal” (id. at
8).
The government’s
brief thereafter makes essentially two legal arguments.
First, it contends
that the right secured by the Second Amendment is “only one which exists where
the arms are borne in the militia or some other military organization provided
for by law and intended for the protection of the state.” Id. at 15. This, in essence, is the sophisticated
collective rights model.
The second
of the government’s two arguments in Miller is reflected by the following
passage from its brief:
“While some
courts have said that the right to bear arms includes the right of the
individual to have them for the protection of his person and property as well as
the right of the people to bear them collectively (People v. Brown, 253
Mich. 537; State v. Duke, 42 Tex. 455), the cases are unanimous in
holding that the term “arms” as used in constitutional provisions refers only to
those weapons which are ordinarily used for military or public defense purposes
and does not relate to those weapons which are commonly used by criminals. Thus in Aymette v. State [2
Humph., Tenn. 154 (1840)], supra, it was said (p.
158):
‘As the object
for which the right to keep and bear arms is secured, is of general and public
nature, to be exercised by the people in a body, for their common
defence, so the arms, the right to keep which is secured, are such as
are usually employed in civilized warfare, and that constitute the ordinary
military equipment. If the citizens
have these arms in their hands, they are prepared in the best possible manner to
repel any encroachments upon their rights by those in authority. They need not, for such a purpose, the
use of those weapons which are usually employed in private broils, and which are
efficient only in the hands of the robber and the assassin. These weapons would be useless in
war. They could not be employed
advantageously in the common defence of the citizens. The right to keep and bear them, is not,
therefore, secured by the constitution.’”
(Id. at 18-19).[16]
The government’s
Miller brief then proceeds (at pp. 19-20) to cite various other state
cases, and Robertson v. Baldwin, 17 S.Ct. 326, 329 (1897),[17]
in support of its second argument, and
states:
“That the
foregoing cases conclusively establish that the Second Amendment has relation
only to the right of the people to keep and bear arms for lawful purposes
and does not conceivably relate to weapons of the type referred to in the
National Firearms Act cannot be doubted.
Sawed-off shotguns, sawed-off rifles and machine guns are clearly weapons
which can have no legitimate use in the hands of private
individuals.”
Thereafter, the
government’s brief in its “conclusion” states: “. . . we respectfully submit that
Section 11 of the National Firearms Act does not infringe ‘the right of the
people to keep and bear arms’ secured by the Second
Amendment.”
Miller reversed the
decision of the district court and “remanded for further proceedings.” Id. at 820. We believe it is entirely clear that the
Supreme Court decided Miller on the basis of the government’s
second argument–that a “shotgun having a barrel of less than eighteen
inches in length” as stated in the National Firearms Act is not (or cannot
merely be assumed to be) one of the “Arms” which the Second Amendment prohibits
infringement of the right of the people to keep and bear–and not on the
basis of the government’s first argument (that the Second Amendment
protects the right of the people to keep and bear no character of “arms”
when not borne in actual, active service in the militia or some other military
organization provided for by law”).
Miller expresses its holding, as
follows:
“In the absence
of any evidence tending to show that possession or use of a ‘shotgun having a
barrel of less than eighteen inches in length’ at this time has some reasonable
relationship to the preservation or efficiency of a well regulated militia, we
cannot say that the Second Amendment guarantees the right to keep and bear
such an instrument.
Certainly it is not within judicial notice that this weapon is any part
of the ordinary military equipment or that its use could contribute to the
common defense. Aymette v. State
of Tennessee, 2 Humph., Tenn. 154, 158.” Id. at 818 (emphasis
added).
Note that the
cited page of Aymette (p. 158) is the page from which the government’s
brief quoted in support of its second argument (see text at call for n.16
supra).[18]
Nowhere in the
Court’s Miller opinion is there any reference to the fact that the
indictment does not remotely suggest that either of the two defendants was ever
a member of any organized, active militia, such as the National Guard, much less
that either was engaged (or about to be engaged) in any actual military service
or training of such a militia unit when transporting the sawed-off shotgun from
Oklahoma into Arkansas. Had the
lack of such membership or engagement been a ground of the decision in
Miller, the Court’s opinion would obviously have made mention of it. But it did not.[19]
Nor do we believe
that any other portion of the Miller opinion supports the sophisticated
collective rights model.
Just after the
above quoted portion of its opinion, the Miller court continued in a
separate paragraph initially quoting the militia clauses of article 1, § 8
(clauses 15 and 16)[20]
and concluding:
“With obvious
purpose to assure the continuation and render possible the effectiveness of such
forces [militia] the declaration and guarantee of the Second Amendment were
made. It must be interpreted and
applied with that end in view.”
Id. at 818.
Miller then proceeds to
discuss what was meant by the term “militia,” stating in part:
“The
signification attributed to the term Militia appears from the debates in the
Convention, the history and legislation of Colonies and States, and the writings
of approved commentators. These
show plainly enough that the Militia comprised all males physically
capable of acting in concert for the common defense. . . . ordinarily when
called for service these men were expected to appear bearing arms supplied by
themselves and of the kind in common use at the
time.
. .
.
“The American
Colonies In the 17th Century,” Osgood, Vol. 1, ch. XIII, affirms in reference to
the early system of defense in New England–
“In all the
colonies, as in England, the militia system was based on the principle of the
assize of arms. This implied the
general obligation of all adult male inhabitants to possess arms, and,
with certain exceptions, to cooperate in the work of defence.’” Id. at
818 (emphasis added).
“The General
Court of Massachusetts, January Session 1784 (Laws and Resolves 1784, c. 55, pp.
140, 142), provided for the organization and government of the Militia. It directed that the Train Band should
‘contain all able bodied men, from sixteen to forty years of age,
and the Alarm List, all other men under sixty years of age, * * *.’”
Id. at 819 (emphasis added).
These passages
from Miller suggest that the militia, the assurance of whose continuation
and the rendering possible of whose effectiveness Miller says were
purposes of the Second Amendment, referred to the generality of the civilian
male inhabitants throughout their lives from teenage years until old age and to
their personally keeping their own arms, and not merely to individuals during
the time (if any) they might be actively engaged in actual military service or
only to those who were members of special or select
units.
We conclude that
Miller does not support the government’s collective rights or
sophisticated collective rights approach to the Second Amendment. Indeed, to the extent that Miller
sheds light on the matter it cuts against the government’s position. Nor does the government cite any other
authority binding on this panel which mandates acceptance of its position
in this respect.[21] However, we do not proceed on the
assumption that Miller actually accepted an individual rights, as opposed
to a collective or sophisticated collective rights, interpretation of the Second
Amendment. Thus, Miller
itself does not resolve that issue.[22] We turn, therefore, to an analysis
of history and wording of the Second Amendment for guidance. In undertaking this analysis, we are
mindful that almost all of our sister circuits have rejected any individual
rights view of the Second Amendment.
However, it respectfully appears to us that all or almost all of these
opinions seem to have done so either on the erroneous assumption that
Miller resolved that issue or without sufficient articulated examination
of the history and text of the Second Amendment.
C. Text
We begin
construing the Second Amendment by examining its text: “[a] well regulated
Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the
people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed.” U.S. Const. amend.
II.
1. Substantive Guarantee
a. “People”
The states rights
model requires the word “people” to be read as though it were “States” or
“States respectively.” This would
also require a corresponding change in the balance of the text to something like
“to provide for the militia to keep and bear arms.” That is not only far removed from the
actual wording of the Second Amendment, but also would be in substantial tension
with Art. 1, § 8, Cl. 16 (Congress has the power “To provide for . . . arming .
. . the militia. . .”). For the
sophisticated collective rights model to be viable, the word “people” must be
read as the words “members of a select militia”.[23] The individual rights model, of course,
does not require that any special or unique meaning be attributed to the word
“people.” It gives the same meaning
to the words “the people” as used in the Second Amendment phrase “the right of
the people” as when used in the exact same phrase in the contemporaneously
submitted and ratified First and Fourth Amendments.
There is no
evidence in the text of the Second Amendment, or any other part of the
Constitution, that the words “the people” have a different connotation within
the Second Amendment than when employed elsewhere in the Constitution. In fact, the text of the Constitution,
as a whole, strongly suggests that the words “the people” have precisely the
same meaning within the Second Amendment as without. And, as used throughout the
Constitution, “the people” have “rights” and “powers,” but federal and state
governments only have “powers” or “authority”, never “rights.”[24] Moreover, the Constitution’s text
likewise recognizes not only the difference between the “militia” and “the
people” but also between the “militia” which has not been “call[ed] forth” and
“the militia, when in actual service.”[25]
Our view of the
meaning of “the people,” as used in the Constitution, is in harmony with the
United States Supreme Court’s pronouncement in United States v.
Verdugo-Urquidez, 110 S.Ct. 1056, 1060-61 (1990),
that:
“‘[T]he people’
seems to have been a term of art employed in select parts of the
Constitution. The Preamble declares
that the Constitution is ordained and established by ‘the People of the United
States.’ The Second Amendment
protects ‘the right of the people to keep and bear Arms,’ and the Ninth and
Tenth Amendments provide that certain rights and powers are retained
by
and reserved to
‘the people.’ While this textual
exegesis is by no means conclusive, it suggests that ‘the people’ protected by
the Fourth Amendment, and by the First and Second Amendments, and to whom rights
and powers are reserved in the Ninth and Tenth Amendments, refers to a class of
people who are part of a national community or who have otherwise developed
sufficient connection with this country to be considered part of that
community.” (citations omitted)
Several other
Supreme Court opinions speak of the Second Amendment in a manner plainly
indicating that the right which it secures to “the people” is an individual or
personal, not a collective or quasi-collective, right in the same sense that the
rights secured to “the people” in the First and Fourth Amendments, and the
rights secured by the other provisions of the first eight amendments, are
individual or personal, and not collective or quasi-collective, rights. See, e.g., Planned Parenthood v.
Casey, 112 S.Ct. 2791, 2805 (1992); Moore v. City of East Cleveland,
97 S.Ct. 1932, 1937 (1977);[26]
Robertson v. Baldwin, supra (see quotation in note 17
supra); Scott v. Sandford, 60 U.S. (19 How) 393, 417, 450-51, 15
L.Ed. 691, 705, 719 (1856). See
also Justice Black’s concurring opinion in Duncan v. Louisiana, 88
S.Ct. 1444, 1456 (1968).[27]
It appears clear
that “the people,” as used in the Constitution, including the Second Amendment,
refers to individual Americans.
b. “Bear Arms”
Proponents of the
states’ rights and sophisticated collective rights models argue that the phrase
“bear arms” only applies to a member of the militia carrying weapons during
actual militia service. Champions
of the individual rights model opine that “bear arms” refers to any carrying of
weapons, whether by a soldier or a civilian. There is no question that the phrase
“bear arms” may be used to refer to the carrying of arms by a soldier or
militiaman. The issue is whether
“bear arms” was also commonly used to refer to the carrying of arms by a
civilian.
The best evidence
that “bear arms” was primarily used to refer to military situations comes from
Aymette v. State, 2 Humph., Tenn. 154 (1840), a prosecution for carrying
a concealed bowie knife. The
Supreme Court of Tennessee, in construing section 26 of its declaration of
rights, providing that “the free white men of this State have a right to keep
and bear arms for their common defence,” stated:
“The 28th section
of our bill of rights provides ‘that no citizen of this State shall be compelled
to bear arms provided he will pay an equivalent, to be ascertained by law.’ Here we know that the phrase has a
military sense, and no other; and we must infer that it is used in the same way
in the 26th section, which secures to the citizen the right to bear arms. A man in pursuit of deer, elk, and
buffaloes might carry his rifle every day for forty years, and yet it would
never be said of him that he had borne arms . . . .”
Unlike the
Tennessee constitution at issue in Aymette, the Second Amendment has no
“for their common defence” language and the United States Constitution contains
no provision comparable to section 28 of the Tennessee constitution on which the
Aymette court relied.
Amici supporting
the government also cite other examples of state constitutional provisions
allowing a conscientious objector to be excused from the duty of bearing arms if
he pays an equivalent so that another can serve in his place.[28]
However, there
are numerous instances of the phrase “bear arms” being used to describe a
civilian’s carrying of arms. Early
constitutional provisions or declarations of rights in at least some ten
different states speak of the right of the “people” [or “citizen” or “citizens”]
“to bear arms in defense of themselves [or “himself”] and the state,” or
equivalent words, thus indisputably reflecting that under common usage “bear
arms” was in no sense restricted to bearing arms in military service.[29] And such provisions were enforced on the
basis that the right to bear arms was not restricted to bearing arms
during actual military service.
See Bliss v. Commonwealth, 13 Am. Dec. 251, 12 Ky. 90 (Ky.
1822).
We also note that
a minority of the delegates to the Pennsylvania ratification convention proposed
the following amendment to the Constitution:
“That the people
have a right to bear arms for the defense of themselves and their own state, or
the United States, or for the purpose of killing game; and no law shall be
passed for disarming the people or any of them, unless for crimes committed, or
real danger of public injury from individuals; and as standing armies in the
time of peace are dangerous to liberty, they ought not to be kept up; and that
the military shall be kept under strict subordination to and be governed by the
civil powers.”
2 Documentary History of the Ratification of the
Constitution 623-24 (Merill Jensen ed., 1976). This is yet another example of “bear
arms” being used to refer to the carrying of arms by civilians for non-military
purposes. Also revealing is a bill
drafted by Thomas Jefferson and proposed to the Virginia legislature by James
Madison (the author of the Second Amendment) on October 31, 1785, that would
impose penalties upon those who violated hunting laws if they “shall bear a gun
out of his [the violator’s] inclosed ground, unless whilst performing military
duty.” 2 The Papers of Thomas Jefferson 443-44
(J.P. Boyd, ed. 1950). A similar
indication that “bear arms” was a general description of the carrying of arms by
anyone is found in the 1828 edition of Webster’s American Dictionary of the
English Language; where the third definition of bear reads: “[t]o wear;
to bear as a mark of authority or distinction, as, to bear a sword, a badge, a
name; to bear arms in a coat.”
We conclude that
the phrase “bear arms” refers generally to the carrying or wearing of arms. It is certainly proper to use the phrase
in reference to the carrying or wearing of arms by a soldier or militiaman;
thus, the context in which “bear arms” appears may indicate that it refers to a
military situation, e.g. the conscientious objector clauses cited by amici
supporting the government. However,
amici’s argument that “bear arms” was exclusively, or even usually, used to
only refer to the carrying or wearing of arms by a soldier or militiaman
must be rejected.[30] The appearance of “bear Arms” in the
Second Amendment accords fully with the plain meaning of the subject of the
substantive guarantee, “the people,” and offers no support for the proposition
that the Second Amendment applies only during periods of actual military service
or only to those who are members of a select militia. Finally, our view of “bear arms” as used
in the Second Amendment appears to be the same as that expressed in the
dissenting opinion of Justice Ginsburg (joined by the Chief Justice and Justices
Scalia and Souter) in Muscarello v. United States, 118 S.Ct. 1911, 1921
(1998); viz:
“Surely a most
familiar meaning [of carrying a firearm] is, as the Constitution’s Second
Amendment (“keep and bear Arms”) (emphasis added) and Black’s Law
Dictionary, at 214, indicate: “wear, bear, or carry . . . upon the person or in
the clothing or in a pocket, for the purpose . . . of being armed and ready for
offensive or defensive action in a case of conflict with another
person.”
c. “Keep . . . Arms”
Neither the
government nor amici argue that “keep . . . Arms” commands a military
connotation.[31] The plain meaning of the right of the
people to keep arms is that it is an individual, rather than a collective, right
and is not limited to keeping arms while engaged in active military service or
as a member of a select militia such as the National
Guard.
d. Substantive Guarantee as a
Whole
Taken as a whole,
the text of the Second Amendment’s substantive guarantee is not suggestive of a
collective rights or sophisticated collective rights interpretation, and the
implausibility of either such interpretation is enhanced by consideration of the
guarantee’s placement within the Bill of Rights and the wording of the other
articles thereof and of the original Constitution as a
whole.
2. Effect of Preamble
We turn now to
the Second Amendment’s preamble: “A well-regulated Militia, being necessary to
the security of a free State.” And,
we ask ourselves whether this preamble suffices to mandate what would be an
otherwise implausible collective rights or sophisticated collective rights
interpretation of the amendment. We
conclude that it does not.
Certainly, the
preamble implies that the substantive guarantee is one which tends to enable,
promote or further the existence, continuation or effectiveness that
“well-regulated Militia” which is “necessary to the security of a free
State.” As the Court said in
Miller, immediately after quoting the militia clauses of Article 1, § 8
(cl. 15 and 16), “[w]ith obvious purpose to assure the continuation and render
possible the effectiveness of such forces the declaration and guarantee of the
Second Amendment were made.”
Id., 59 S.Ct. at 818.
We conclude that the Second Amendment’s substantive guarantee, read as
guaranteeing individual rights, may as so read reasonably be understood as being
a guarantee which tends to enable, promote or further the existence,
continuation or effectiveness of that “well-regulated Militia” which is
“necessary to the security of a free State.” Accordingly, the preamble does not
support an interpretation of the amendment’s substantive guarantee in accordance
with the collective rights or sophisticated collective rights model, as such an
interpretation is contrary to the plain meaning of the text of the guarantee,
its placement within the Bill of Rights and the wording of the other articles
thereof and of the original Constitution as a whole.[32]
As observed in
Miller, “the Militia comprised all males physically capable of acting in
concert for the common defense” and
“that ordinarily when called for service these men were expected to
appear bearing arms supplied by themselves.” Id., 59 S.Ct. at 818. Miller further notes that “‘[i]n
all the colonies . . . the militia systems . . . implied the general obligation
of all adult male inhabitants to possess arms.’” Id. (citation
omitted).[33] There are frequent contemporaneous
references to “a well-regulated militia” being “composed of the body of the
people, trained in arms.”[34] Plainly, then, “a well-regulated
Militia” refers not to a special or select subset or group taken out of
the militia as a whole but rather to the condition of the militia as a whole,
namely being well disciplined and trained.[35] And, “Militia,” just like
“well-regulated Militia,” likewise was understood to be composed of the people
generally possessed of arms which they knew how to use, rather than to refer to
some formal military group separate and distinct from the people at large.[36] Madison also plainly shared these views,
as is reflected in his Federalist No. 46 where he argued that power of Congress
under the proposed constitution “[t]o raise and support Armies” (art. 1, § 8,
cl.12) posed no threat to liberty because any such army, if misused, “would be
opposed [by] a militia amounting to near half a million of citizens with arms in
their hands” and then noting “the advantage of being armed, which the Americans
possess over the people of almost every other nation,” in contrast to “the
several kingdoms of Europe” where “the governments are afraid to trust the
people with arms.” The Federalist
Papers at 299 (Rossiter, New American Library). Plainly, Madison saw an armed
people as a foundation of the militia which would provide security for a “free”
state, one which, like America but unlike the “kingdoms of Europe,” was not
afraid to trust its people to have their own arms.[37] The militia consisted of the people
bearing their own arms when called to active service, arms which they kept and
hence knew how to use. If the
people were disarmed there could be no militia (well-regulated or otherwise) as
it was then understood. That
expresses the proper understanding of the relationship between the Second
Amendment’s preamble and its substantive guarantee. As stated in Kates, Handgun
Prohibition and the Original Meaning of the Second Amendment, supra
n.12, “the [second] amendment’s wording, so opaque to us, made perfect sense to
the Framers: believing that a militia (composed of the entire people possessed
of their individually owned arms) was necessary for the protection of a free
state, they guaranteed the people’s right to possess those arms.” Id. at 217-18. Similarly, Cooley, General Principles of Constitutional
Law (Little, Brown, 1880; 1981 Rothman & Co. reprint) rejects, as
“not warranted by the intent,” an interpretation of the Second Amendment “that
the right to keep and bear arms was only guaranteed to the Militia,” and states
“[t]he meaning of the provision undoubtedly is, that the people, from whom the
militia must be taken, shall have the right to keep and bear arms; and they need
no permission or regulation of law for the purpose. But this enables the government to have
a well-regulated militia; for to bear arms implies something more than the mere
keeping; it implies the learning to handle and use them in a way that makes
those who keep them ready for their efficient use.” Id. at 271. Much the same thought was expressed more
than one hundred years later in the following passage from Tribe, American Constitutional Law (3d ed.
2000):
“Perhaps the most
accurate conclusion one can reach with any confidence is that the core meaning
of the Second Amendment is a populist/republican/federalism one: Its central
object is to arm “We the People” so that ordinary citizens can participate in
the collective defense of their community and their state. But it does so not through directly
protecting a right on the part of states or other collectivities, assertable by
them against the federal government, to arm the populace as they see fit. Rather, the amendment achieves its
central purpose by assuring that the federal government may not disarm
individual citizens without some unusually strong justification consistent with
the authority of the states to organize their own militias. That assurance in turn is provided
through recognizing a right (admittedly of uncertain scope) on the part of
individuals to possess and use firearms in the defense of themselves and their
homes . . . a right that directly limits action by Congress or by the Executive
Branch . . .” Id., Vol. 1,
n.221 at 902.
In sum, to give
the Second Amendment’s preamble its full and proper due there is no need to
torture the meaning of its substantive guarantee into the collective rights or
sophisticated collective rights model which is so plainly inconsistent with the
substantive guarantee’s text, its placement within the bill of rights and the
wording of the other articles thereof and of the original constitution as a
whole.
D. History
1. Introduction
Turning to the
history of the Second Amendment’s adoption, we find nothing inconsistent with
the conclusion that as ultimately proposed by Congress and ratified by the
states it was understood and intended in accordance with the individual rights
model as set out above.
On May 25, 1787,
the Federal Convention began meeting in Philadelphia to craft what would become
the United States Constitution. The primary shortcoming of the Articles of
Confederation was that the central government it provided for was too weak. It was generally recognized that,
although a stronger central government was needed, the central government was to
remain one of limited and enumerated powers only, lest the cure be worse than
the disease. Thus, the challenge
was to design a federal government strong enough to deal effectively with that
particular range of issues requiring federal control, without enabling the
federal government to become an instrument of tyranny. Not surprisingly, political leaders of
that day differed as to the proper balance of these concerns. The Federalists favored a strong federal
government. The Anti-Federalists
were much more suspicious and fearful of a strong federal government and wanted
numerous safeguards in place to protect the people and the states from being
tyrannized and oppressed by the federal government. The Federal Convention was dominated by
the Federalists. On September 17,
1787, the Convention completed its work and forwarded the Constitution to the
Confederation Congress.
2. The Anti-Federalists’
Fears
The Constitution
alarmed Anti-Federalists for three reasons relevant to the debate over the
meaning of the Second Amendment.
First, although
the proposed federal government appeared to be one of limited and enumerated
powers, the Anti-Federalists feared that it would someday attempt to infringe
one or more of the people’s fundamental rights. To help prevent this, the
Anti-Federalists wanted the United States Constitution, like most of the state
Constitutions, to contain a Bill of Rights.[38]
Second, the
Constitution gave the federal government large powers over the militia, allowing
the Congress:
“To provide for
calling forth the Militia to execute the Laws of the Union, suppress
Insurrections and repel Invasions;
To provide for
organizing, arming, and disciplining, the Militia, and for governing such Part
of them as may be employed in the Service of the United States, reserving to the
States respectively, the Appointment of the Officers, and the Authority of
training the Militia according to the discipline prescribed by
Congress;”.
U.S.
Const. art. 1, § 8, cl.
15, 16. Congress was also given the
power “To raise and support Armies.”
Id. art. 1 § 8, cl. 12.
The states were also forbidden to keep troops without the consent of
Congress. Id. art. 1, § 10,
cl. 3.
The
Anti-Federalists feared that the federal government would act or fail to act so
as to destroy the militia, e.g. failure to arm the militia,[39]
disarmament of the militia[40],
failure to prescribe training for the militia[41],
creation of a select militia[42]
or making militia service so unpleasant that the people would demand a standing
army or select militia.[43] These concerns over the militia were
exacerbated by the third issue: the federal government’s power to maintain a
standing army (art. 1, § 8, cl.12).
The Anti-Federalists feared that the federal government’s standing army
could be used to tyrannize and oppress the American people.[44] Without a militia to defend against the
federal government’s standing army, the states and their citizens would be
defenseless.[45]
Thus, the
Anti-Federalists wanted the Constitution amended in three ways prior to
ratification: 1) addition of a Bill of Rights; 2) recognition of the power of
the states to arm and train their militias;[46]
and 3) curtailment of the federal government’s power to maintain a standing
army.
3. The Federalist Response
The Federalists,
of course, wanted the Constitution to be ratified. Because the Constitution could only be
ratified unchanged, this forced the Federalists to oppose all attempts to alter
it prior to ratification. The
Federalists argued that no bill of rights was needed for three reasons: 1) it
was beyond the purview of the federal government, intended to be one of limited
and enumerated powers, to infringe upon fundamental rights;[47]
2) any enumeration of fundamental rights might imply that the federal government
had power to infringe upon those not mentioned;[48]
and 3) the American people were used to being free–they would not allow their
rights to be infringed.[49]
Realizing that
the Anti-Federalists’ two other concerns
(federal control of arming and training of the militia and maintenance of
a standing army) boiled down to a fear that the federal government’s standing
army would oppress a defenseless people, the Federalists’ responded that: 1) the
American people are armed and hence could successfully resist an oppressive
standing army;[50]
and 2) federal militia powers obviated the need for, or minimized the likelihood
of, a large standing army being kept in existence.[51]
The Federalists
also responded to the militia issue by arguing that the states had concurrent
power to arm the militia, but this position was undermined when the
Anti-Federalists invited the Federalists to put that state power in writing and
that would have necessitated the return to the drawing board in another
Constitutional convention that the Federalists were committed to avoiding.[52]
The Federalist
position as to the militia and standing army issues depended upon the people
being armed notwithstanding that the Constitution did not guarantee the right of
the people to be armed.[53]
4. State Ratifications
Congress
forwarded the Constitution to the states on September 28, 1787. State conventions began considering the
Constitution later that year. By
April 28, 1788, Delaware, New Jersey, Georgia, Connecticut and Maryland had
ratified the Constitution without proposing any additions or changes to it. The first sign of trouble in a state
convention was in Pennsylvania in December of 1787.
a. Pennsylvania
In the
Pennsylvania convention, the Federalists outnumbered the Anti-Federalists about
two to one. Not surprisingly, then,
on December 12, 1787, the Pennsylvania convention ratified the Constitution by a
vote of 46 to 23. The convention
did not propose any changes to the Constitution. However, the disenchanted
Anti-Federalists, known as the Pennsylvania Minority, explained that they would
have agreed to the Constitution if it had been amended to reflect fourteen
principles, among which were the following:
“7. That the
people have a right to bear arms for the defense of themselves and their own
state, or the United States, or for the purpose of killing game; and no law
shall be passed for disarming the people or any of them, unless for crimes
committed, or real danger of public injury from individuals; and as standing
armies in the time of peace are dangerous to liberty, they ought not to be kept
up; and that the military shall be kept under strict subordination to and be
governed by the civil power.
....
11. That the
power of organizing, arming, and disciplining the militia (the manner of
disciplining the militia to be prescribed by Congress) remain with the
individual states, and that Congress shall not have authority to call or march
any of the militia out of their own state, without the consent of such state and
for such length of time only as such state shall agree.”
2 The Documentary History of the Ratification of
the Constitution 623-24 (Merrill Jensen, ed. 1976). Note that “bear arms” clearly pertains
to private, civilian wearing or carrying of arms and the power of the state to
organize, arm and discipline the militia is in a separate section, indicating
that the Anti-Federalists viewed these issues as distinct.
b. Massachusetts
Massachusetts
ratified the Constitution on February 7, 1788, by a vote of 187 to 168. Although the convention proposed nine
amendments, none of them has relevance to the issues with which we are
concerned. However, during the
Massachusetts convention, Samuel Adams proposed the following
amendments:
“And that the
said Constitution be never construed to authorize Congress to infringe the just
liberty of the press, or the rights of conscience; or to prevent the people of
the United States, who are peaceable citizens, from keeping their own arms; or
to raise standing armies, unless when necessary for the defense of the United
States, or of some one or more of them; or to prevent the people from
petitioning, in a peaceable and orderly manner, the federal legislature, for a
redress of grievances; or to subject the people to unreasonable searches and
seizures of their persons, papers or possessions.”
Debates
of the Massachusetts Convention of 1788 86-87, 266
(Boston, 1856). This is another
indication that the Anti-Federalists desired protection for the right of all
peaceful citizens to keep arms as well as a limitation on the power of the
federal government to maintain a large standing army.
c. South Carolina
The South
Carolina Convention ratified the Constitution on May 23, 1788, stating two
understandings and proposing two amendments, none of which are relevant to the issues
before us.
d. New Hampshire
After adjourning
on February 22, 1788, to avoid rejection of the Constitution, New Hampshire
ratified the Constitution on June 21, 1788, by a vote of 57 to 47. The New Hampshire convention proposed
twelve amendments, the first nine of which are identical to Massachusetts’. New Hampshire’s proposed Amendments 10
and 12 were as follows:
“X. That no
standing army shall be kept up in time of peace, unless with the consent of
three-fourths of the members of each branch of Congress; nor shall soldiers, in
time of peace, be quartered upon private houses, without the consent of the
owners.
....
XII. Congress
shall never disarm any citizen, unless such as are or have been in actual
rebellion.”
1 Jonathan Elliot, The Debates in the Several State Conventions
on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution 326 (2d ed., 1836). New Hampshire sought to protect the
individual right of all citizens to have arms and, separately, to limit the
power of the federal government to maintain a large standing
army.
e. Virginia
On June 25, 1788,
the Virginia convention ratified the Constitution by a vote of 89 to 79. The convention proposed a bill of rights
containing twenty separate provisions and, in a separate section, proposed
twenty amendments to the Constitution.
The seventeenth part of Virginia’s proposed Bill of Rights and the ninth
and eleventh parts of its proposed amendments to the Constitution were as
follows:
[Bill of Rights
section.]
17th. That the
people have a right to keep and bear arms; that a well-regulated militia,
composed of the body of the people trained to arms, is the proper, natural, and
safe defence of a free state; that standing armies, in time of peace, are
dangerous to liberty, and therefore ought to be avoided, as far as the
circumstances and protection of the community will admit; and that, in all
cases, the military should be under strict subordination to, and governed by,
the civil power.
[Amendments to
the Constitution section.]
9th. That no
standing army, or regular troops, shall be raised, or kept up, in time of peace,
without the consent of two thirds of the members present, in both
houses.
11th. That each
state respectively shall have the power to provide for organizing, arming, and
disciplining its own militia, whensoever Congress shall omit or neglect to
provide for the same. That the
militia shall not be subject to martial law, except when in actual service, in
time of war, invasion, or rebellion; and when not in the actual service of the
United States, shall be subject only to such fines, penalties, and punishments,
as shall be directed or inflicted by the laws of its own
state.
3 Jonathan Elliot, The Debates in the Several State Conventions
on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution 658, 660 (2d ed., 1836). The bill of rights provision,
after stating “[t]hat the people have a right to keep and bear arms,”
goes on to make general, philosophical observations about the militia and
standing armies. However, these
general, philosophical observations are given their legal effectuation through
separate, specific provisions apart from the Bill of Rights. The Virginia convention realized that
statements in the proposed Bill of Rights that militias are good and standing
armies are bad fell short of adding to the power of the states or subtracting
from the power of the federal government.
In the separate and distinct amendments section, the states were
explicitly given militia powers and the federal government was forbidden to
maintain a standing army unless other specific criteria were
satisfied.
f. New York
On July 26, 1788,
New York ratified the Constitution by a vote of 30 to 27. New York incorporated an extensive
Declaration of Rights and thirty-three proposed amendments to the Constitution
into its ratification. The relevant
portions of each are:
[Declaration of
Rights section.]
“That the people
have a right to keep and bear arms; that a well-regulated militia, including the
body of the people capable of bearing arms, is the proper, natural, and
safe defence of a free state.
...
That standing
armies, in time of peace, are dangerous to liberty, and ought not to be kept up,
except in cases of necessity; and that at all times the military should be under
strict subordination to the civil power.
[Amendments to
the Constitution section.]
That no standing
army or regular troops shall be raised, or kept up, in time of peace, without
the consent of two thirds of the senators and representatives present in each
house.”
1 Jonathan Elliot, The Debates in the Several State Conventions
on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution 328, 330 (2d ed., 1836). Note that: 1) the philosophical
declaration concerning the preferability of a militia, which follows the
statement “[t]hat the people have a right to keep and bear arms,” is not
effectuated in the amendments section by a grant of power to the states to
maintain a militia; and 2) there is a separate clause in the Declaration of
Rights section regarding standing armies which is effectuated by a
separate proposed amendment to the Constitution. This is another example that
philosophical declarations alone were considered insufficient to subtract from
the federal government’s power or to add to the states’
power.
g. North Carolina
On August 1,
1788, North Carolina refused to ratify the Constitution until a bill of rights
and other amendments were added.
The North Carolina convention demanded the same Bill of Rights and
amendments as proposed by Virginia.
It was not until November 21, 1789, after the Bill of Rights was
forwarded by the First Congress to the states, that North Carolina finally
ratified the Constitution by a vote of 194-77.
h. Rhode Island
Rhode Island did
not ratify the Constitution until May 29, 1790, and then by a vote of
34-32. Rhode Island incorporated a
bill of rights into its ratification and proposed twenty-one amendments to the
Constitution. The apposite portions
of each are:
[Declaration of
Rights section.]
“XVII. That the
people have a right to keep and bear arms; that a well-regulated militia,
including the body of the people capable of bearing arms, is the proper,
natural, and safe defence of a free state; that the militia shall not be subject
to martial law, except in time of war, rebellion, or insurrection; that standing
armies, in time of peace, are dangerous to liberty, and ought not to be kept up,
except in cases of necessity; and that, at all times, the military should be
under strict subordination to the civil power; that, in time of peace, no
soldier ought to be quartered in any house without the consent of the owner, and
in time of war only by the civil magistrates, in such manner as the law
directs.
[Amendments to
the Constitution section.]
XII. As standing
armies, in time of peace, are dangerous to liberty, and ought not to be kept up,
except in cases of necessity, and as, at all times, the military should be under
strict subordination to the civil power, that, therefore, no standing army or
regular troops shall be raised or kept up in time of
peace.”
Id. at 335-36. Note how even the amendment regarding
standing armies contains two philosophical declarations before getting to the
substantive restriction on federal power, namely that no army shall be
maintained during peacetime.
5. Proposal of Second
Amendment
By mid 1788, the
required nine states had ratified the Constitution, and it was clear the
Federalists had won a major victory.
But by the spring of 1789, the Anti-Federalists had succeeded in
persuading many that a bill of rights was absolutely necessary. Some Anti-Federalists did continue to
argue for additional, structural changes to the Constitution, but most were
primarily concerned with a bill of rights.
At the same time, while some Federalists continued to reject any changes
to the Constitution, most softened their opposition to a bill of rights, mindful
of the strong public support for it and aware that a bill of rights would not
materially affect the plan of government they had worked so diligently to
implement. See President
George Washington, Inaugural Address, April 30, 1789 (excerpt reprinted
in Young, supra note 34, at 642) (“I assure myself that whilst you
carefully avoid every alteration which might endanger the benefits of an united
and effective government, or which ought to await the future lessons of
experience; a reverence for the characteristic rights of freemen, and a regard
for the public harmony, will sufficiently influence your deliberations on the
question how far the former can be more impregnably fortified, or the latter be
safely and advantageously promoted.”); Letter from Charles Smith to Tench Coxe
(October 18, 1788) (excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at
542) (“It seems, therefore, to be the wish of the moderate and reasonable men of
all parties that some necessary explanations should take place, in order to
quiet the minds of our dissenting fellow citizens, and to introduce union and
harmony throughout the state.
Attention to this subject ought to be considered as a duty incumbent upon
our first federal Representatives.”).
Thus, as there sometimes is after a hard-fought political struggle, most
of the combatants, for the good of the country, sought middle
ground.
Federalist James
Madison ran for a seat in the First Congress, and because of the strong public
support for a bill of rights clarified his own support for
it:
“The offer of my
services to the district, rests on the following grounds:–That although I
always conceived the constitution might be improved, yet I never could
see in it, as it stands, the dangers which have alarmed many respectable
citizens; that I held it my duty therefore, whilst the constitution remained
unratified, and it was necessary to unite the various opinions, interests and
prejudices of the different states, in some one plan, to oppose every previous
amendment, as opening a door for endless and dangerous contentions among the
states, and giving an opportunity to the secret enemies of the union to promote
its dissolution:–That the change of circumstances produced by the secure
establishment of the plan proposed, leaves me free to espouse such amendments as
will, in the most satisfactory manner, guard essential rights, and will render
certain vexatious abuses of power impossible . . .”
James Madison,
Extract of a letter from the Hon. JAMES MADISON, jun. to his friend in
this county, Fredericksburg Virginia
Herald, January 29, 1788 (reprinted in Young, supra note
34, at 609). The Federalists ended
up with a majority in both the House and the Senate. But as the eventual adoption of a bill
of rights shows, many Federalists were as open to a bill of rights as James
Madison himself was. See
Letter from James Madison to Edmund Pendleton (April 8, 1789) (excerpt
reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 640) (“The subject of
amendments has not yet been touched–From appearances there will be no great
difficulty in obtaining reasonable ones.
It will depend however entirely on the temper of the federalists, who
predominate as much in both branches, as could be wished. Even in this State [Virginia],
notwithstanding the violence of its antifederal symptoms, three of its six
representatives at least will be zealous friends to the Constitution, and it is
not improbable that a fourth will be of the same description.”). The Anti-Federalists sensed that
although the tide had turned their way as to alterations that would secure
individual liberty, the prospects for other changes to the Constitution were
dim. See Letter from Richard
Henry Lee to Patrick Henry (May 28, 1789)
(excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 644)(“I
think, from what I hear and see, that many of our amendments will not succeed,
but my hopes are strong that such as may effectually secure civil liberty will
not be refused.”).
a. Legislative
History
On June 8, 1789,
Virginia Congressman James Madison proposed several alterations to the
Constitution in the First Congress.
In his address to the House, Madison explained his rationale in proposing
the changes:
“I wish, among
other reasons why something should be done, that those who have been friendly to
the adoption of this constitution may have the opportunity of proving to those
who were opposed to it that they were as sincerely devoted to liberty and a
Republican Government, as those who charged them with wishing the adoption of
this constitution in order to lay the foundation of an aristocracy or
despotism. It will be a desirable
thing to extinguish from the bosom of every member of the community, any
apprehension that there are those among his countrymen who wish to deprive them
of the liberty for which they valiantly fought and honorably bled. And if there are amendments desired of
such a nature as will not injure the constitution, and they can be ingrafted so
as to give satisfaction to the doubting part of our fellow-citizens, the friends
of the Federal Government will evince that spirit of deference and concession
for which they have hitherto been distinguished.
....
I should be
unwilling to see a door opened for a re-consideration of the whole structure of
the Government–for a re-consideration of the principles and the substance of the
powers given; because I doubt, if such a door were opened, we should be very
likely to stop at that point which would be safe to the Government itself. But I do wish to see a door opened to
consider, so far as to incorporate those provisions for the security of rights,
against which I believe no serious objection has been made by any class of our
constituents: such as would be likely to meet with the concurrence of two-thirds
of both Houses, and with the approbation of three-fourths of the State
Legislatures.”
James Madison,
House of Representatives, June 8, 1789 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
supra note 34, at 651-53).
Madison proposed to insert, in Article 1, Section 9, between its Clauses
3 and 4, the following clause (among
others):
“The right of the
people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed; a well armed and well
regulated militia being the best security of a free country; but no person
religiously scrupulous of bearing arms shall be compelled to render military
service in person.”[54]
Id. at 654-55. Article 1, Section 9 contains nothing
but restrictions upon the power of the federal government; and its Clauses 2 and
3 relate only to individual rights (habeas corpus, bill of attainder and ex post
facto).
Madison’s
proposal was eventually submitted to a House committee of eleven members, of
which Madison was one. That
committee issued its report on July 28, 1789. The clause that would become the Second
Amendment then read:
“A well regulated
militia, composed of the body of the people, being the best security of a free
state, the right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed, but
no person religiously scrupulous shall be compelled to bear arms.” House of Representatives, Proceedings on
Amendments, July 28, 1789 (reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at
680-82).
Thus, the
philosophical declaration was moved to precede the substantive guarantee and
“composed of the body of the people” was added just after
“militia.”
The House began
its consideration of what would become the Second Amendment on August 17,
1789. Congressman Gerry moved to
strike the religiously scrupulous exemption. See House of Representatives,
Debate, August 17, 1789 (excerpt
reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 695-99). This motion was defeated by a vote of
24-22; however, this language would later be dropped by the Senate. Opponents of the individual rights model
find hope in the initial appearance of the religiously scrupulous exemption and
comments made by Congressman Gerry in attempting to excise it. They argue that because “bear arms” has
a military connotation in the religiously scrupulous clause, it necessarily
carries the same meaning in the substantive guarantee. This construction is supported, we are
told, by Gerry’s objection. Gerry
feared that the federal government would use the clause to destroy the militia
by declaring a large number of people religiously scrupulous and, therefore,
ineligible for militia service.
This would pave the way for oppression by the federal government’s
standing army.
“This declaration
of rights, I take it, is intended to secure the people against the
mal-administration of the Government; if we could suppose that, in all cases,
the rights of the people would be attended to, the occasion for guards of this
kind would be removed. Now, I am
apprehensive, sir, that this clause would give an opportunity to the people in
power to destroy the constitution itself.
They can declare who are those religiously scrupulous, and prevent them
from bearing arms.
What, sir, is the
use of a militia? It is to prevent
the establishment of a standing army, the bane of liberty. Now, it must be evident, that, under
this provision, together with their other powers, Congress could take such
measures, with respect to a militia, as to make a standing army necessary. Whenever governments mean to invade the
rights and liberties of the people, they always attempt to destroy the militia,
in order to raise an army upon their ruins.”
Id. at 695-96. Gerry concluded by proclaiming, “[n]ow,
if we give a discretionary power to exclude those from militia duty who have
religious scruples, we may as well make no provision on this head.”[55] The inference urged is that the only
purpose of the substantive guarantee was to secure the right of militia members
to bear arms in a military context.
This interpretation of Gerry’s statements appears somewhat strained. We think that Gerry’s comments
manifested his opinion that: 1) it takes a well regulated militia, not the mere
private possession of firearms, to obviate the need for a standing army; and 2)
an armed populace offers much less protection against a standing army than a
well regulated militia. If Gerry
saw any conflict between the amendment’s substantive guarantee and the
destruction of the militia which was supposedly enabled by the religiously
scrupulous clause, he did not say so.
In fact, Gerry’s objection assumes that the amendment does not increase
state power over the militia and that the preamble is but a philosophical
declaration as to the necessity of a well regulated militia that does nothing to
disturb Art. 1, § 8, cl. 16, to which Gerry must be referring to as the source
of the power of the federal government to destroy the militia. Gerry’s concern was directed to the
creation of a standing army; he does not express any worry that the feared
purging of the rolls of the militia would enable the federal government to
confiscate privately owned firearms, no doubt because the substantive guarantee
applies to all the people, not just those that at a given time might comprise
the militia. Properly understood,
Gerry’s remarks are not inconsistent with the individual rights view of the
Second Amendment.
Gerry was not the
only member of the First Congress to express concern over the religiously
scrupulous clause. Three days
later, on August 20, 1789, Congressman Scott complained of it as
well.
“Mr. Scott
objected to the clause in the sixth amendment, ‘No person religiously scrupulous
shall be compelled to bear arms.’
He observed that if this becomes part of the constitution, such persons
can neither be called upon for their services, nor can an equivalent be
demanded; it is also attended with still further difficulties, for a militia can
never be depended upon. This would
lead to the violation of another article in the constitution, which secures to
the people the right of keeping arms, and in this case recourse must be had to a
standing army.”
House of
Representatives, Debates, August 20, 1789
(excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 703). Congressman Boudinot opposed striking
the clause, in part because such action would imply the federal government is
going to “compel all its citizens to bear arms.” Id. The House ended up adding “in person” to
the end of the clause.
Id. We find no
meaningful support, in Congressman Scott’s statement, for either the states’
rights or the sophisticated collective rights models. Scott was not concerned, as Gerry was,
that the federal government would use the religiously scrupulous clause as a
ruse to exclude everyone from militia service. Scott was worried that too many
individual Americans would avail themselves of the clause’s protection and that
this would cause the militia to be so weakened that the federal government would
have no choice but to maintain a standing army. It is not exactly clear where Scott
found violation of the people’s right to keep arms. The lack of a dependable militia both
leads to Scott’s hypothetical violation and necessitates recourse to a standing
army. It is possible that Scott
found, in the amendment’s philosophical declaration, some sort of right of the
people to be free from a standing army.[56] In any case, this cryptic passage does
not plainly lend support to any of the Second Amendment models. The only change that resulted from this
discussion was the addition of the words “in person” at the end of the amendment
and, as mentioned, the entire religiously scrupulous clause was later deleted by
the Senate.
Congressman Burke
repeatedly proposed that a clause be added to the amendment that would have
required the consent of two-thirds of both houses of Congress to maintain a
standing army in time of peace.
This proposal was defeated by a margin of almost two to one. House of Representatives, Debates,
August 17, 1789 (excerpt
reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 697-98).
On August 24,
1789, the House completed its work on the proposed amendments and forwarded them
to the Senate. At this time, the
amendment read:
“A well regulated
militia, composed of the body of the people, being the best security of a free
state, the right of the people to keep and bear arms, shall not be infringed,
but no one religiously scrupulous of bearing arms, shall be compelled to render
military service in person.”
House of
Representatives, Proceedings, August 24, 1789 (excerpt reprinted in
Young, supra note 34, at 707).
The Senate, which had the House action
before it from August 25 through September 9, 1789, made three changes: 1) the
words “composed of the body of the people” were stricken; 2) the words “the
best” were replaced by “necessary to the”; and 3) the entire religiously
scrupulous clause was stricken.
See The Complete Bill of
Rights 173-76 (Neil H. Cogan, ed., 1997). The Senate debates were conducted in
secret, so there is no direct evidence of why these changes were made. The Senate rejected a proposed amendment
to add the words “for the common defense” just after “the right of the people to
keep and bear arms”.
Id. Like the House,
the Senate rejected a proposed amendment that would have required the consent of
two-thirds of both houses of Congress to maintain a standing army in time of
peace. Id. The Senate on
September 8, 1789 also refused to adopt an amendment that would have given the
states power to arm and train their militias.[57]
The most
significant Senate action is the rejection of the amendment that would have
granted the power of the states to arm and train their own militias. This is, of course, the precise effect
the states’ rights model attributes to the Second Amendment. Proponents of that model argue that the
rejection of that amendment simply indicates that this concern was already
addressed, i.e. that the rejected amendment would have been mere
surplusage. This is highly
implausible, particularly given the Second Amendment’s placement within the Bill
of Rights, its “the right of the people” language identical to that of the First
and Fourth Amendments, and its lack of any reference to the power or rights of
the states, all as contrasted to the direct and explicit state power language of
the rejected amendment. Moreover,
this surplusage explanation also ignores that in the state conventions the right
to keep and bear arms was always in the Bill of Rights section of proposed
changes, while the state power to arm and train the militia was always in a
separate section or at least a separate article.
Not surprisingly,
the significance of the Senate’s other alterations or rejections is open to
question. It could be argued that
the striking of the words “composed of the body of the people” supports the
sophisticated collective rights view that “militia” in the Second Amendment
really means “select militia” and, therefore, pertains only to our modern
national guard. However, there is
an abundance of historical evidence that indicates the Anti-Federalists abhorred
the idea of a select militia every bit as much as a standing army.[58] Clearly, if the Anti-Federalists
believed the amendment offered any support for the formation of a select
militia, or only recognized the right of members of the select militia to keep
and bear arms while on active duty, they would have vociferously opposed
it. It must be remembered that the
entire goal of submitting amendments was to pacify, not infuriate, the
Anti-Federalists. This suggests
that the words “composed of the body of the people” were stricken as unnecessary
surplusage.
The replacement
of “best” with “necessary to the” strengthens the philosophical declaration’s
support for a militia. As the
rejection of standing army amendments in the House and Senate, as well as
subsequent history, show, even this bolder statement did not serve to limit the
power of the federal government to maintain a large standing army. Probably the only bearing this change
has on the task before this Court is that it makes the sophisticated collective
rights model’s contention that “militia” really means national guard or “select
militia” even more questionable.
Anti-Federalists would never have accepted that a select militia was the
best security (or anything but a threat to) “a free state,” much less
necessary to the security of “a free
state.”
Opponents of the
individual rights model claim the Senate refused to add “for the common defense”
after the amendment’s substantive guarantee because those words were unnecessary
surplusage. Given the amendment’s
text and history, which, almost without exception, support the individual rights
view, we believe it much more likely that the Senate rejected this language
because it potentially posed the risk of an interpretation contracting the
substantive guarantee.
Finally, perhaps
the least relevant Senate change is the deletion of the religiously scrupulous
clause. This may well have been
because the Senate felt that the clause was not sufficiently germane to an
amendment whose core purpose was to state the affirmative rights of individuals
as opposed to limitations on their potential obligations, or, relatedly, that
the clause dealt with a relatively minor, collateral matter which was not worth
the controversy and/or confusion it had generated or could generate. Or, the Senate might simply have felt
(as did Congressman Benson, see note 55 supra) this would be better left
to the wisdom and discretion of a future Congress.
The House
approved the Senate version of the amendment, and Congress forwarded it to the
states along with the rest of the Bill of Rights on September 26, 1789.[59]
b. Political Discourse
At the same time
the above legislative history was being made, prominent Americans were writing
in the newspapers and to each other.
These writings provide some insight into the nature (individual or
collective) of the Second Amendment.
Anti-Federalist
William Grayson expressed concern to fellow Anti-Federalist Patrick Henry that
the only amendments that would be approved are those, like Madison’s, that
recognize individual rights:
“I am exceedingly
sorry it is out of my power to hold out to you any flattering expectations on
the score of amendments; it appears to me that both houses are almost wholly
composed of federalists; those who call themselves Antis are so extremely
lukewarm as scarcely to deserve the appellation: Some gentlemen here from
motives of policy have it in contemplation to effect amendments which shall
effect personal liberty alone, leaving the great points of the judiciary, direct
taxation &c, to stand as they are . . . . Last Monday a string of amendments were
presented to the lower House; these altogether respected personal liberty . . .
.”
Letter from
William Grayson to Patrick Henry (June 12, 1789) (excerpt reprinted in
Young, supra note 34, at 668-69).
Federalist Fisher
Ames was pleased that Madison’s amendments primarily concerned noncontroversial
individual rights.
“Mr. Madison has
inserted, in his amendments, the increase of representatives, each State having
two at least. The rights of
conscience, of bearing arms, of changing the government, are declared to be
inherent in the people. Freedom of
the press, too. There is a
prodigious great dose of medicine.
But it will stimulate the stomach as little as hasty-pudding. It is rather food than physic. Am [sic] immense mass of sweet and other
herbs and roots for a diet drink.”
Letter from
Fisher Ames to George Richards Minot (June 12, 1789) (excerpt reprinted
in Young, supra note 34, at 668).
Federalist Tench
Coxe, in a widely republished article, described what would become the Second
Amendment this way:
“As civil rulers,
not having their duty to the people, duly before them, may attempt to tyrannize,
and as the military forces which shall be occasionally raised to defend our
country, might pervert their power to the injury of their fellow-citizens, the
people are confirmed by the next article in their right to keep and bear their
private arms.”
A Pennsylvanian
[Federalist Tench Coxe], REMARKS on the first part of the AMENDMENTS
to the FEDERAL CONSTITUTION, moved on the 8th instant in the House of
Representatives, Philadelphia Federal Gazette, June 18, 1789
(excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 671). That same day, Coxe wrote to Madison,
discussing public reaction to Madison’s proposed amendments and his own comments
thereon which appeared in the Federal Gazette. See Young, supra note 34,
at 672. Madison
responded:
“Accept my
acknowledgments for your favor of the 18th. instant. The printed remarks inclosed in it are
already I find in the Gazettes here.
It is much to be wished that the discon[ten]ted part of our fellow
Citizens could be reconciled to the Government they have opposed, and by means
as little as possible unacceptable to those who approve the Constitution in its
present form. The amendments
proposed in the H. of Reps. had this twofold object in view; besides the third
one of avoiding all controvertible points which might endanger the assent of 2/3
of each branch of Congs and 3/4 of the State Legislatures. How far the experiment may succeed in
any of these respects, is wholly uncertain. It will however be greatly favored by
explanatory strictures of a healing tendency, and is therefore already indebted
to the co-operation of your pen.”
Letter from James
Madison to Tench Coxe (June 24, 1789) (excerpt reprinted in Young,
supra note 34, at 673-74).
Thus, consistent with his other statements, Madison seems to have
endorsed Coxe’s individual rights explanation of what would become the Second
Amendment. Note that Coxe made no
mention of the philosophical declaration regarding a well regulated militia, but
only referred to the provision’s substantive guarantee and also that Coxe’s
reference to “private arms” is essentially inconsistent with both the states’
rights and sophisticated collective rights models.
Opponents of the
individual rights view dispute that Madison’s letter was an endorsement of
Coxe’s explanation of the amendments, claiming that Madison disagreed with
Coxe’s explanation of the right of conscience. In other words, they say that Madison
was just being polite to Coxe for his attempt to explain the amendments and may
not have agreed with all of the positions Coxe took. Two problems with this view are that
there is no evidence that anybody disagreed with Coxe’s explanation of
the Second Amendment and that Madison’s notes for his speech supporting the
amendments indicate that they “relate 1st to private rights”. James Madison, Notes for speech in
Congress supporting Amendments (June 8, 1789) (reprinted in Young,
supra note 34, at 645).
Joseph Jones, in
a letter to James Madison, wrote:
“I thank you for
the copy of the amendments proposed to the constitution which you lately
inclosed to me–they are calculated to secure the personal rights of the people
so far as declarations on paper can effect the purpose, leaving unimpaired the
great Powers of the government–they are of such a nature as to be generally
acceptable and of course more likely to obtain the assent of Congress that wod.
any proposition tending to separate the powers or lessen them in either
branch.”
Letter from
Joseph Jones to James Madison (June 24, 1789) (excerpt reprinted in
Young, supra note 34, at 673).
Surely Mr. Jones would have distinguished an amendment that did not
secure “personal rights.”
Anti-Federalist
Samuel Nasson recognized that the amendment guaranteed the right of individuals
to keep arms for any lawful purpose.
“I find that
Amendments are once again on the Carpet.
I hope that such may take place as will be for the Best Interest of the
whole[.] A Bill of rights well secured that we the people may know how
far we may Proceade in Every Department[,] then their [sic] will be no Dispute
between the people and rulers[.] [I]n that may be secured the right to keep
arms for Common and Extraordinary Occations such as to secure ourselves against
the wild Beast and also to amuse us by fowling and for our Defence against a
Common Enemy[.] [Y]ou know to learn the Use of arms is all that can Save us
from a forighn foe that may attempt to subdue us[,] for if we keep up the Use
of arms and become well acquainted with them we Shall allway be able to look
them in the face that arise up against us[,] for it is impossible to Support
a Standing armey large Enough to Guard our Lengthy Sea
Coast[.]”
Letter from
Samuel Nasson to George Thatcher (July 9, 1789) (excerpt reprinted in
Young, supra note 34, at 796-97) (emphasis
added).
While Congressman
Fisher Ames, a very strong Federalist, was pleased that Madison’s amendments
seemed unlikely to cause discord, he also expressed chagrin that the amendments
were so focused on protecting the rights of the rabble that they did not belong
in the Constitution.
“We have had the
amendments on the tapis, and referred them to a committee of one from a
State. I hope much debate will be
avoided by this mode, and that the amendments will be more rational, and less
ad populum, than Madison’s.
It is necessary to conciliate, and I would have amendments. But they should not be trash, such as
would dishonor the Constitution, without pleasing its enemies. Should we propose them, North Carolina
would accede. It is doubtful, in
case we should not.”
Letter from
Fisher Ames to George Richards Minot (July 23, 1789) (excerpt reprinted
in Young, supra note 34, at 679).
Congressman
William L. Smith viewed the Bill of Rights as recognizing individual rights, not
the structure of government.
“The Committee on
amendmts. have reported some, which are thought inoffensive to federalists &
may do some good on the other side: N. Car[olin]a. only wants some pretext to
come into the Union, & we may afford that pretext by recommending a few
amendments.
There appears to
be a disposition in our house to agree to some, which will more effectually
secure private rights, without affecting the structure of
Govt.”
Letter from
William L. Smith to Edward Rutledge (August 9, 1789) (excerpt reprinted
in Young, supra note 34, at 798) (emphasis
added).
Pennsylvania
Congressman Frederick A. Muhlenberg believed the Bill of Rights would placate
“our Minority in Pennsylvania.”
“Altho’ I am
sorry that so much Time has been spent in this Business [the Bill of Rights],
and would much rather have had it postponed to the next Session, yet as it
now is done I hope it will be satisfactory to our State, and as it takes in the
principal Amendments which our Minority had so much at Heart, I hope it may
restore Harmony & unanimity amongst our fellow Citizens . . .
.”
Letter from
Frederick A. Muhlenberg to Benjamin Rush (August 18, 1789) (excerpt reprinted
in Young, supra note 34, at 799) (emphasis added). Recall that the Pennsylvania Minority
proposed what was indisputably an individual right to keep and bear
arms.
Some
Anti-Federalists were upset that Federalist James Madison was getting all the
credit for proposing the Bill of Rights.
They believed much of this credit was due Samuel Adams. Recall that Adams unsuccessfully
proposed his own set of amendments to the Massachusetts Convention (and was much
criticized for making the attempt).
“It may well be
remembered that the following ‘amendments’ to the new constitution for these
United States, were introduced to the convention of this commonwealth by its
present Lieutenant Governor, that venerable patriot, SAMUEL ADAMS.–It was his
misfortune to have been misconceived, and the proposition was accordingly
withdrawn–lest the business of the convention (the session of which was then
drawing to a period) might be unexpectedly protracted. His enemies triumphed exceedingly, and
affected to represent his proposal as not only an artful attempt to prevent the
constitution being adopted in this state, but as an unnecessary and improper
alteration of a system, which did not admit of improvements. To the honor of this gentlemen’s
penetration, and of his just way of thinking on this important subject, every
one of his intended alterations, but one, have been already reported by the
committee of the House of Representatives in Congress, and most probably will be
adopted by the federal legislature.
In justice therefore to that long tried Republican, and his numerous
friends, you gentlemen, are requested to re-publish his intended alterations, in
the same paper that exhibits to the public, the amendments which the committee
have adopted, in order that they may be compared
together.”
Letter from
Mssrs. Adams & Nourse to the Editor of the Boston Independent
Chronicle, Philadelphia Independent
Gazetteer, August 20, 1789 (reprinted in Young, supra note
34, at 701-702). This is
significant because Adams’ amendments prohibited the constitution from ever
being construed to “prevent the people of the United States who are peaceable
citizens, from keeping their own arms.”
Id. This language is
not at all susceptible to the states’ rights or sophisticated collective rights
views.
Many
Anti-Federalists supported the Bill of Rights, notwithstanding that it fell far
short of delivering what they had fought for in the state conventions. But at least one famous Anti-Federalist
was enraged that the amendments did not alter the balance of power between the
federal and state governments, particularly as to control over the
militia.
“What would be
your opinion of the man who, living where thieves were so numerous and vigilant
as to improve every opportunity of plunder, should go to sleep at night in
thoughtless security, with his doors wide open . .
.
Similar would be
the conduct of the people of the United States, if they rest the security of
their invaluable privileges upon the partial amendments making by Congress to
the new constitution: for although many of these amendments are very proper and
necessary, yet whilst the constitution is suffered to retain powers that may not
only defeat their salutary operation, but may, and incontrovertibly will be so
decisively injurious as to sweep away every vestige of liberty; it is an insult
upon the understanding and discernment of the people to flatter them with the
secure enjoyment of privileges, that are held by so precarious and transient a
tenure.
Besides, some of
these limited, insecure amendments, which, to a superficial observer, seem to
contain useful provisions, when examined with attention, are found to be
delusive and inoperative. I will
instance two or three of them.
....
Article
5th of the proposed amendments–‘A well regulated militia, composed of
the body of the people, being the best security of a free state, the right of
the people to keep and bear arms, shall not be infringed, &c.’ It is remarkable that this article only
makes the observation, ‘that a well regulated militia, composed of the
body of the people, is the best security of a free state;’ it does not
ordain, or constitutionally provide for, the establishment of such a one. The absolute command vested by other
sections in Congress over the militia, are not in the least abridged by this
amendment. The militia may still be
subjected to martial law and all its concomitant severities, and disgraceful
punishments, may still be marched from state to state and made the unwilling
instruments of crushing the last efforts of expiring
liberty.”
Centinel,
Revived, No. XXIX, Philadelphia Independent Gazetteer, September 9,
1789 (excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 711-12). Extreme Anti-Federalists like the
Centinel would not be placated by mere recognition of a right about which the
Federalists and Anti-Federalists were in agreement: the right of the people to
keep and bear arms. In the
Centinel’s view, as long as the federal government had such extensive power over
the militia, the people’s liberties were not safe. The Centinel simply rejected the
Federalists repeated argument that there was no need to worry about a standing
army as long as individuals were armed.
The Centinel also correctly observed that the amendment’s preamble did
nothing to alter the balance (or imbalance) of power between the state and
federal governments as to the militia.
6. 19th Century Commentary
The great
Constitutional scholars of the 19th Century recognized that the Second Amendment
guarantees the right of individual Americans to possess and carry firearms. We list their contributions in the order
in which they were made. First, St.
George Tucker:
“8. A well
regulated militia being necessary to the security of a free state, the right of
the people to keep and bear arms, shall not be infringed. Amendments to C.U.S. Art.
4.
This may be
considered as the true palladium of liberty. . . . The right of self defence is
the first law of nature: in most governments it has been the study of rulers to
confine this right within the narrowest limits possible. Wherever standing armies are kept up,
and the right of the people to keep and bear arms is, under any colour or
pretext whatsoever, prohibited, liberty, if not already annihilated, is on the
brink of destruction. In England,
the people have been disarmed, generally, under the specious pretext of
preserving the game: a never failing lure to bring over the landed aristocracy
to support any measure, under that mask, though calculated for very different
purposes. True it is, their bill of
rights seems at first view to counteract this policy: but the right of bearing
arms is confined to protestants, and the words suitable to their condition and
degree, have been interpreted to authorise the prohibition of keeping a gun or
other engine for the destruction of game, to any farmer, or inferior tradesman,
or other person not qualified to kill game. So that not one man in five hundred can
keep a gun in his house without being subject to a
penalty.”
1
St. George Tucker, Blackstone’s Commentaries: with Notes of Reference, to the
Constitution and Laws, of the Federal Government of the United States; and of
the Commonwealth of Virginia, 300 (1803)
(ellipsis in original). Note how
the fact that the Second Amendment applies to Americans generally is sharply
contrasted with, and favorably compared to, the relevant part of the English
Bill of Rights, which only pertained to Protestants and even for those only as
“suitable to their condition and degree.”
The Amendment is said to facilitate the right of self defense. Having individuals armed is particularly
necessary when standing armies are kept up, as the combination of a standing
army and a disarmed populace threatens the destruction of
liberty.
Second, William
Rawle:
“In the second
article, it is declared, that a well regulated militia is necessary to the
security of a free state; a proposition from which few will dissent. Although in actual war, the services of
regular troops are confessedly more valuable; yet, while peace prevails, and in
the commencement of a war before a regular force can be raised, the militia form
the palladium of the country. They
are ready to repel invasion, to suppress insurrection, and preserve the good
order and peace of government. That
they should be well regulated, is judiciously added. A disorderly militia is disgraceful to
itself, and dangerous not to the enemy, but to its own country. The duty of the state government is, to
adopt such regulations as will tend to make good soldiers with the least
interruptions of the ordinary and useful occupations of civil life. In this all the Union has a strong and
visible interest.
The corollary,
from the first position, is, that the right of the people to keep and bear
arms shall not be infringed.
The prohibition
is general. No clause in the
Constitution could by any rule of construction be conceived to give to congress
a power to disarm the people. Such
a flagitious attempt could only be made under some general pretence by a state
legislature. But if in any blind
pursuit of inordinate power, either should attempt it, this amendment may be
appealed to as a restraint on both.
In most of the
countries of Europe, this right does not seem to be denied, although it is
allowed more or less sparingly, according to circumstances. In England, a country which boasts so
much of its freedom, the right was secured to protestant subjects only, on the
revolution of 1688; and it is cautiously described to be that of bearing arms
for their defence, ‘suitable to their conditions, and as allowed by law.’ An arbitrary code for the preservation
of game in that country has long disgraced them. A very small proportion of the people
being permitted to kill it, though for their own subsistence; a gun or other
instrument, used for that purpose by an unqualified person, may be seized and
forfeited. Blackstone, in whom we
regret that we cannot always trace the expanded principles of rational liberty,
observes however, on this subject, that the prevention of popular insurrections
and resistence to government by disarming the people, is oftener meant than
avowed, by the makers of forest and game laws.
This right ought
not, however, in any government, to be abused to the disturbance of the public
peace.
An assemblage of
persons with arms, for an unlawful purpose, is an indictable offence, and even
the carrying of arms abroad by a single individual, attended with circumstances
giving just reason to fear that he purposes to make an unlawful use of them,
would be sufficient cause to require him to give surety of the peace. If he refused he would be liable to
imprisonment.”
William
Rawle, A View of the Constitution of the United States of America 125-26 (Da Capo
Press 1970) (2d ed. 1829) (footnotes omitted). This explanation recognizes that the
preamble is a declaration, a “proposition,” setting forth the desirability of
reliance upon a militia during peacetime.
A well-regulated militia is the opposite of a disorderly, disgraceful
militia. Rawle also observes that
the Amendment’s substantive guarantee applies to all Americans –“[t]he
prohibition is general.” He
likewise makes plain that it precludes legislation “to disarm the people.” Rawle, like St. George Tucker, makes
clear that the Second Amendment does not suffer from the infirmities of the
corresponding part of the English Bill of Rights.
Next, Justice
Joseph Story:
“§ 1000. The next
amendment is: “A well regulated militia being necessary to the security of a
free state, the right of the people to keep and bear arms shall not be
infringed.
§ 1001. The importance of this article
will
scarcely be
doubted by any persons, who have duly reflected upon the subject. The militia is the natural defence of a
free country against sudden foreign invasions, domestic insurrections, and
domestic usurpations of power by rulers.
It is against sound policy for a free people to keep up large military
establishments and standing armies in time of peace, both from the enormous
expenses, with which they are attended, and the facile means, which they afford
to ambitious and unprincipled rulers, to subvert the government, or trample upon
the rights of the people. The
right of the citizens to keep, and bear arms has justly been considered, as the
palladium of the liberties of a republic; since it offers a strong moral check
against the usurpation and arbitrary power of rulers; and will
generally, even if these are successful in the first instance, enable the
people to resist, and triumph over them. And yet, though this truth would seem so
clear, and the importance of a well regulated militia would seem so undeniable,
it cannot be disguised, that among the American people there is a growing
indifference to any system of militia discipline, and a strong disposition, from
a sense of its burthens, to be rid of all regulations. How it is practicable to keep the
people duly armed without some organization, it is difficult to see. There is certainly no small danger, that
indifference may lead to disgust, and disgust to contempt; and thus gradually
undermine all the protection intended by this clause of our national bill of
rights.”
Joseph
Story, Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States 708-709
(Carolina Academic Press 1987) (1833) (emphasis added). Justice Story calls the right of
“citizens” to keep and bear arms the “palladium” of our liberties. He viewed the private ownership of
firearms as reducing the need for the maintenance of large standing armies by
promoting the vitality of the militia, and laments that militia participation is
on the decline, fearing this will result in fewer Americans being
armed.
And finally,
Thomas Cooley:
“Section IV.—The Right to Keep and Bear
Arms
The
Constitution.—By the second
amendment to the Constitution it is declared that, ‘a well-regulated militia
being necessary to the security of a free state, the right of the people to keep
and bear arms shall not be infringed.’
The amendment,
like most other provisions in the Constitutions, has a history. It was adopted with some modification
and enlargement from the English Bill of Rights of 1688, where it stood as a
protest against arbitrary action of the overturned dynasty in disarming the
people, and as a pledge of the new rulers that this tyrannical action should
cease. The right declared was meant
to be a strong moral check against the usurpation and arbitrary power of rulers,
and as a necessary and efficient means of regaining rights when temporarily
overturned by usurpation.
The Right is
General.—It might be
supposed from the phraseology of this provision that the right to keep and bear
arms was only guaranteed to the militia; but this would be an interpretation not
warranted by the intent. The
militia, as has been elsewhere explained, consists of those persons who, under
the law, are liable to the performance of military duty, and are officered and
enrolled for service when called upon.
But the law may make provision for the enrolment of all who are fit to
perform military duty, or of a small number only, or it may wholly omit to make
any provision at all; and if the right were limited to those enrolled, the
purpose of this guaranty might be defeated altogether by the action or
neglect to act of the government it was meant to hold in check. The meaning of the provision
undoubtedly is, that the people, from whom the militia must be taken, shall have
the right to keep and bear arms; and they need no permission or regulation
of law for the purpose. But this
enables the government to have a well-regulated militia; for to bear arms
implies something more than the mere keeping; it implies the learning to handle
and use them in a way that makes those who keep them ready for their
efficient use; in other words, it implies the right to meet for voluntary
discipline in arms, observing in doing so the laws of public
order.
Standing
Army.—A further
purpose of this amendment is, to preclude any necessity or reasonable excuse for
keeping up a standing army. A
standing army is condemned by the traditions and sentiments of the people, as
being as dangerous to the liberties of the people as the general preparation of
the people for the defence of their institutions with arms is preservative of
them.
What Arms may be
kept.—The arms
intended by the Constitution are such as are suitable for the general defence of
the community against invasion or oppression, and the secret carrying of those
suited merely to deadly individual encounters may be
prohibited.”
Thomas
M. Cooley, The General Principles of Constitutional Law in the United States of
America 270-72 (Rothman
& Co. 1981) (original ed. 1880) (footnotes omitted) (emphasis
added).
7.
Analysis
The history we
have recounted largely speaks for itself.
We briefly summarize. The
Anti-Federalists desired a bill of rights, express provision for increased state
power over the militia, and a meaningful express limitation of the power of the
federal government to maintain a standing army. These issues were somewhat
interrelated. The prospect of
federal power to render the militia useless and to maintain a large standing
army combined with the absence of any specific guarantees of individual liberty
frightened Anti-Federalists. But
the Anti-Federalist complaint that resonated best with the people at large was
the lack of a bill of rights.
In mid-1788 the
Constitution was ratified unchanged and in the spring of 1789 the Federalists
gained control of both houses of the First Congress. Hard core Anti-Federalists persisted in
all three demands, but more moderate Anti-Federalists and the people at large
were primarily focused on securing a bill of rights. Most Federalists were not really averse
to a bill of rights, but, like James Madison himself, had been forced to oppose
any modifications to the Constitution since it could only be ratified
unchanged. The Federalists wanted
to please the Anti-Federalists as much as possible without fundamentally
altering the balance of federal-state power. James Madison plainly stated this goal
when he submitted his proposed amendments to the
House.
Given the
political dynamic of the day, the wording of the Second Amendment is exactly
what would have been expected. The
Federalists had no qualms with recognizing the individual right of all Americans
to keep and bear arms. In fact, as
we have documented, one of the Federalists’ favorite 1787-88 talking points on
the standing army and federal power over the militia issues was to remind the
Anti-Federalists that the American people were armed and hence could not
possibly be placed in danger by a federal standing army or federal control over
the militia. The Second Amendment’s
preamble represents a successful attempt, by the Federalists, to further pacify
moderate Anti-Federalists without actually conceding any additional ground, i.e.
without limiting the power of the federal government to maintain a standing army
or increasing the power of the states over the militia.
This is not to
say that the Second Amendment’s preamble was not appropriate or is in any way
marginal or lacking in true significance.
Quite the contrary. Absent a
citizenry generally keeping and bearing their own private arms, a militia as it
was then thought of could not meaningfully exist. As pointed out by Thomas Cooley, the
right of individual Americans to keep, carry, and acquaint themselves with
firearms does indeed promote a well-regulated militia by fostering the
development of a pool of firearms-familiar citizens that could be called upon to
serve in the militia. While
standing armies are not mentioned in the preamble, history shows that the reason
a well-regulated militia was declared necessary to the security of a free
state was because such a militia would greatly reduce the need for a standing
army. Thus, the Second Amendment
dealt directly with one of the Anti-Federalists’ concerns and indirectly
addressed the other two. While the
hard core Anti-Federalists recognized that the Second Amendment did not assure a
well-regulated militia or curtail the federal government’s power to maintain a
large standing army, they did not control either branch of Congress (or the
presidency) and had to be content with the right of individuals to keep and bear
arms.
Finally, the many
newspaper articles and personal letters cited indicate that, at the time,
Americans viewed the Second Amendment as applying to individuals. This is confirmed by the First
Congress’s rejection of amendments that would have directly and explicitly
addressed the Anti-Federalists’ standing army and power over the militia
concerns.
We have found no
historical evidence that the Second Amendment was intended to convey militia
power to the states, limit the federal government’s power to maintain a standing
army, or applies only to members of a select militia while on active duty.[60] All of the evidence indicates that the
Second Amendment, like other parts of the Bill of Rights, applies to and
protects individual Americans.
We find that the
history of the Second Amendment reinforces the plain meaning of its text, namely
that it protects individual Americans in their right to keep and bear arms
whether or not they are a member of a select militia or performing active
military service or training.
E. Second Amendment protects individual
rights
We reject the
collective rights and sophisticated collective rights models for interpreting
the Second Amendment. We hold,
consistent with Miller, that it protects the right of individuals,
including those not then actually a member of any militia or engaged in active
military service or training, to privately possess and bear their own firearms,
such as the pistol involved here, that are suitable as personal, individual
weapons and are not of the general kind or type excluded by Miller. However, because of our holding that
section 922(g)(8), as applied to Emerson, does not infringe his individual
rights under the Second Amendment we will not now further elaborate as to the
exact scope of all Second Amendment rights.
VI. Application to
Emerson
The district
court held that section 922(g)(8) was unconstitutionally overbroad because it
allows second amendment rights to be infringed absent any express judicial
finding that the person subject to the order posed a future danger. In other words, the section 922(g)(8)
threshold for deprivation of the fundamental right to keep and bear arms is too
low.[61]
Although, as we
have held, the Second Amendment does protect individual rights, that does
not mean that those rights may never be made subject to any limited, narrowly
tailored specific exceptions or restrictions for particular cases that are
reasonable and not inconsistent with the right of Americans generally to
individually keep and bear their private arms as historically understood in this
country. Indeed, Emerson does not
contend, and the district court did not hold, otherwise. As we have previously noted, it is clear
that felons, infants and those of unsound mind may be prohibited from possessing
firearms. See note 21,
supra.[62] Emerson’s argument that his Second
Amendment rights have been violated is grounded on the propositions that the
September 14, 1998 order contains no express finding that he represents a
credible threat to the physical safety of his wife (or child), that the evidence
before the court issuing the order would not sustain such a finding and that the
provisions of the order bringing it within clause (C)(ii) of section 922(g)(8)
were no more than uncontested boiler-plate. In essence, Emerson, and the district
court, concede that had the order contained an express finding, on the basis of
adequate evidence, that Emerson actually posed a credible threat to the physical
safety of his wife, and had that been a genuinely contested matter at the
hearing, with the parties and the court aware of section 922(g)(8), then Emerson
could, consistent with the Second Amendment, be precluded from possessing a
firearm while he remained subject to the order.[63]
Though we are
concerned with the lack of express findings in the order, and with the absence
of any requirement for same in clause (C)(ii) of section 922(g)(8), we are
ultimately unpersuaded by Emerson’s argument. Section 922(g)(8)(A) requires an actual
hearing with prior notice and an opportunity to participate, and section
922(g)(8)(C)(ii) requires that the order “explicitly” prohibit the use (actual,
threatened or attempted) of physical force that would reasonably be expected to
cause bodily injury. Congress
legislated against the background of the almost universal rule of American law
that for a temporary injunction to issue:
“There must be a
likelihood that irreparable harm will occur. Speculative injury is not sufficient;
there must be more than an unfounded fear on the part of the applicant. Thus, a preliminary injunction will not
be issued simply to prevent the possibility of some remote future injury. A presently existing actual threat
must be shown. However, the
injury need not have been inflicted when application is made or be certain to
occur; a strong threat of irreparable injury before trial is an adequate
basis.” 9 Wright, Miller & Kane, Federal Practice
and Procedure: Civil 2d § 2948.1 at 153-56 (footnotes omitted; emphasis
added).[64]
We conclude that
Congress in enacting section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii) proceeded on the assumption that
the laws of the several states were such that court orders, issued after notice
and hearing, should not embrace the prohibitions of paragraph (C)(ii) unless
such either were not contested or evidence credited by the court reflected a
real threat or danger of injury to the protected party by the party
enjoined. We do not imply that
Congress intended to authorize collateral review of the particular state court
predicate order in section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii) prosecutions to determine whether in
that individual case the state court adequately followed state law in issuing
the order. What we do suggest is
that Congress did not have in mind orders issued under a legal system whose
rules did not approximate the above stated general minimum standards for the
issuance of contested injunctive orders after notice and
hearing.
In any event, it
is clear to us that Texas law meets these general minimum standards. See, e.g., Texas Indus. Gas v.
Phoenix Metallurgical, 828 S.W.2d 529, 532 (Tex. App.-Hou. [1st Dist.]
1992):
“A trial court
may not issue a temporary injunction except to prevent a threatened injury. . .
. The commission of the act to be enjoined must be more than just speculative,
and the injury that flows from the act must be more than just conjectural. . . .
The trial court will abuse its discretion if it grants a temporary injunction
when the evidence does not clearly establish that the applicant is threatened
with an actual, irreparable injury.”
See
also State v.
Morales, 869 S.W.2d 941, 946 (Tex. 1994) (“An injunction will not issue
unless it is shown that the respondent will engage in the activity enjoined”);
Armendariz v. Mora, 526 S.W.2d 542, 543 (Tex. 1975) (reversing temporary
injunction where no “evidence establishing probable injury”); Dallas General
Drivers v. Wamix, 295 S.W.2d 873, 879 (Tex. 1956); In re Marriage of
Spiegel, 6 S.W.3d 643, 645 (Tex. App.-Amarillo
1999).
We conclude that
essentially the same standards are applicable to orders, such as the September
14, 1998 order here, issued under Texas Family Code § 6.502, which provides that
in a pending divorce proceeding “after notice and hearing, the court may render
an appropriate order, including the granting of a temporary injunction for . . .
protection of the parties as deemed necessary . . . including an order directed
to one or both parties . . . prohibiting an act described by Section
6.501(a).” Section 6.501(a),
dealing with temporary restraining orders in divorce proceedings, authorizes
orders “prohibiting one or both parties from: . . . (2) threatening the other,
by telephone or in writing, to take unlawful action against any person,
intending by this action to annoy or alarm the other; . . . (4) intentionally,
knowingly, or recklessly causing bodily injury to the other or to a child of
either party; (5) threatening the other or a child of either party with imminent
bodily injury; . . .” The predecessor statute to section 6.502 has been
construed as requiring a showing of “reasonable necessity” for the temporary
injunction, including a showing of “a probable injury.” See Florence v. Florence, 388
S.W.2d 220, 223-24 (Tex. Civ. App.-Tyler 1965)
We are also
somewhat troubled by the unavailability of review by direct appeal of
interlocutory orders under section 6.502.
See Texas Family Code § 6.507. However, appellate court review is
available by mandamus under an “abuse of discretion” standard. Wallace v. Briggs, 348 S.W.2d
523, 527 (Tex. 1961). There are a
number of reported appellate court decisions granting such relief from orders
under the predecessors to section 6.502.
See, e.g., Wallace; Little v. Daggett, 858 S.W.2d 368 (Tex. 1993);
Dancy v. Daggett, 815 S.W.2d 548 (Tex. 1991); Post v. Garza, 867
S.W.2d 88 (Tex. App.-Corpus Christi 1993).
We also note that it has more generally been said that a “trial court
will abuse its discretion if it grants a temporary injunction when the
evidence does not clearly establish that the applicant is threatened with an
actual, irreparable injury,” Texas Indus. Gas, supra, 828 S.W.2d
at 532 (emphasis added), and that, with reference to ruling on a temporary
injunction application, “[a]n abuse of discretion arises when the trial
court acts without reference to applicable guiding principles . . .; acts
arbitrarily; . . . or misinterprets or misapplies the law. . . .” In Re Marriage of Spiegel, 6
S.W.3d 643, 645 (Tex. App.-Amarillo 1999) (emphasis added; citations
omitted). We also note in this
connection that orders such as that here of September 14, 1998, expire on the
final decree of divorce (and are subject to modification by the trial court
prior thereto; if incorporated into the final divorce decree they are then
subject to review on direct appeal).
In light of the
foregoing, we cannot say that section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii)’s lack of a requirement
for an explicit, express credible
threat finding by the court issuing the order–of itself or together with
appellate court review being available (prior to final judgment) only by
mandamus–renders that section infirm under the Second Amendment. The presence of such an explicit finding
would likely furnish some additional indication that the issuing court
properly considered the matter, but such findings can be as much “boilerplate”
or in error as any other part of such an order.
As to Emerson’s
contention that the evidence before the court issuing the September 14, 1998
order was insufficient to show that he posed a credible threat to the physical
safety of his wife or child, we conclude that under these circumstances Lewis
v. United States, 100 S.Ct. 915 (1980) and our decision in United States
v. Chambers, 922 F.2d 228 (5th Cir. 1991), each discussed in part I hereof
above, necessarily preclude the court in the section 922(g)(8) prosecution from
that sort of collateral review of the validity of the particular section
922(g)(8) predicate order, at least where, as we hold to be the case here, the
order is not so “transparently invalid” as to have “only a frivolous pretense to
validity.” See Chambers at
239.
With respect to
temporary injunctions and similar orders to be issued only after notice and
hearing, the Texas rule of law, as we have noted, is that such an order, at
least to the extent contested and explicitly prohibiting acts such as are
covered by section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii), may not properly issue unless the issuing
court concludes, based on adequate evidence at the hearing, that the party
restrained would otherwise pose a realistic threat of imminent physical injury
to the protected party, and this is so regardless of whether or not Texas law
requires the issuing court to make on the record express or explicit findings to
that effect. Moreover, such orders
are subject to being set aside by the issuing court as well as being subject to
some review by an appellate court.
In such a case, we conclude that the nexus between firearm possession by
the party so enjoined and the threat of lawless violence, is sufficient, though
likely barely so, to support the deprivation, while the order remains in effect,
of the enjoined party’s Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms, and that
this is so even though the party enjoined may not collaterally attack the
particular predicate order in the section 922(g)(8) prosecution, at least so
long as the order, as here, is not so transparently invalid as to have only a
frivolous pretense to validity.[65]
VII. Conclusion
Error has not
been demonstrated in the district court’s refusal to dismiss the indictment on
commerce clause grounds.
For the reasons
stated, we reverse the district court’s order granting the motion to dismiss the
indictment under the Fifth Amendment.
We agree with the
district court that the Second Amendment protects the right of individuals to
privately keep and bear their own firearms that are suitable as individual,
personal weapons and are not of the general kind or type excluded by
Miller, regardless of whether the particular individual is then actually
a member of a militia.[66] However, for the reasons stated, we also
conclude that the predicate order in question here is sufficient, albeit likely
minimally so, to support the deprivation, while it remains in effect, of the
defendant’s Second Amendment rights.
Accordingly, we reverse the district court’s dismissal of the indictment
on Second Amendment grounds.
We remand the
cause for further proceedings not inconsistent herewith.
REVERSED and
REMANDED[67]
Appendix
The material in
this appendix comes largely from Young, “The Origin of the Second Amendment” (2d
Ed. 1995) (Golden Oaks Books), herein after cited as Young (all emphasis in
original unless otherwise noted).
1. Anti-Federalists want a Bill of
Rights.
Letter from
Richard Henry Lee to William Shippen, Jr. (October 2, 1787) (reprinted in
Young, at 31)(“I have considered the new Constitution . . . & I find it
impossible for me to doubt, that in its present State, unamended, the adoption
of it will put Civil Liberty and the happiness of the people at the mercy of
Rulers who may possess the great unguarded powers given . . . The necessary
alterations will by no means interfere with the general nature of the plan, or
limit the power of doing good; but they will restrain from oppression the wicked
& Tyrannic . . . .”); Letter from George Mason to George Washington (October
7, 1787) (reprinted in Young, at 34-35) (“Objections to the Constitution
of Government formed by the Convention.
There is no Declaration of Rights, and the Laws of the general Government
being paramount to the Laws & Constitutions of the several States, the
Declarations of Rights in the separate States are no Security.”); An Old Whig
II, Philadelphia Independent
Gazetteer, October 17, 1787 (excerpts reprinted in Young, at
49-51) (“[T]he future Congress will be fully authorized to assume all such
powers as they in their wisdom or wickedness, according as the one or the other
may happen to prevail, shall from time to time think proper to assume. . . .
[I]t is not of a farthing consequence whether they really are of opinion that
the law is necessary and proper, or only pretend to think so; for who can
overrule their pretensions?–No one, unless we had a bill of rights to which we
might appeal . . . In giving such immense, such unlimited powers, was there no
necessity of a bill of rights to secure to the people their liberties?”); Letter
from Elbridge Gerry to the Massachusetts General Court (October 18, 1787)
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 51) (“My principal objections to the
plan, are . . . that the system is without the security of a bill of rights.”);
An Old Whig III, Philadelphia
Independent Gazetteer, October 20, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in
Young, at 51) (“[T]here ought to be a bill of rights firmly established,
which neither treaties nor acts of the legislature can alter.”); Letter from
Louis Guillaume Otto to Comte de Montmorin (October 21, 1787) (excerpt
reprinted in Young, at 56) (“He [Anti-Federalist Richard Henry Lee]
disapproves especially that the government might have been accorded immense
powers without preceding the Constitution with a bill of rights, which
has always been regarded as the palladium of a free people.”); A
Confederationalist, Philadelphia
Pennsylvania Herald, October 27, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
at 66) (“[A] declaration of those inherent and political rights ought to be made
in a BILL OF RIGHTS, that the people may never lose their liberties by
construction.”); Letter from George Lee Turberville to Arthur Lee (October 28,
1787) (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 71) (“[T]his points out to me the
absolute necessity of a bill of rights–and that a very full & explanatory
one too–where not only the Liberty of the press, the trial by jury of the
vicinage & all those great points–but even every the most trivial privilege
that Citizens have a right to possess–shou’d be expressly stipulated and
reserved–& the violation of them most scrupulously and Jealously guarded
against–Of what consequence is the federal guarantee of republican governments
to the individual states, when the power of the Militia’s even is rested in the
president . . . .”); Letter from Arthur Lee to Edward Rutledge (October 29,
1787) (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 72) (“I do not like it [the
Constitution]. The want of a
promised declaration of rights, when by some exceptions in the Body of it,
things, in which no power is expressly given, implies that every thing not
excepted is given; is a very material defect.); R.S., Philadelphia Pennsylvania Herald,
November 10, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 101) (“The most
repeated, and certainly the most substantial, charge against the proposed
constitution, is the want of a bill of rights.”); Brutus III, New York Journal, November 15, 1787
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 104) (“[T]he plan [the Constitution] is
radically defective in a fundamental principle, which ought to be found in every
free government; to wit, a declaration of rights.”); Robert Whitehill,
Pennsylvania Convention, November 28, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
at 117) (“If indeed the Constitution itself so well defined the powers of
government that no mistake could arise, and we were well assured that our
governors would always act right, then we might be satisfied without an explicit
reservation of those rights with which the people ought not, and mean not to
part. But, sir, we know that it is
the nature of power to seek its own augmentation, and thus the loss of liberty
is the necessary consequence of a
loose or extravagant delegation of authority. National freedom has been, and will be
the sacrifice of ambition and power, and it is our duty to employ the present
opportunity in stipulating such restrictions as are best calculated to protect
us from oppression and slavery.”); A
Federal Republican, A Review of the Constitution (November 28, 1787)
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 119) (“Hitherto we have been considering
the blemishes of the Constitution as they statedly exist–other objects are
derived from omission. Among these
the grand one, upon which is indeed suspended every other, is the omission of a
bill of rights.”); Letter from Thomas Jefferson to James Madison (December 20,
1787) (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 177) (“[A] bill of rights is what
the people are entitled to against every government on earth, general or
particular, & what no just government should refuse, or rest on
inference.”); Letter from Thomas B. Waite to George Thatcher, January 8, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 194) (“There is a certain darkness,
duplicity and studied ambiguity of expression running thro’ the whole
Constitution which renders a Bill of Rights peculiarly necessary.–As it now
stands but very few individuals do, or ever will understand it.–Consequently,
Congress will be its own interpreter . . . .”); Samuel, Boston Independent Chronicle, January 10, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 202) (“The most complaints, that I have
heard made about the proposed Constitution, are that there is no declaration of
rights.”); Hugh Henry Brackenridge, Pittsburgh Gazette, March 1, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 291) (“The want of a bill of
rights is the great evil.”); Luther Martin, Baltimore Maryland Journal, March 21, 1788
(excerpts reprinted in Young, at 306) (“But the proposed constitution
being intended and empowered to act not only on states, but also immediately on
individuals, it renders a recognition and a stipulation in favour of the rights
both of states and of men, not only proper, but in my opinion, absolutely
necessary.”); Patrick Henry, Virginia Convention, June 16, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at
436) (“[T]he necessity of a bill of rights appears to me to be greater in this
government than ever it was in any government before.”).
And, there were
moderates who sought to make peace between the Federalists and Anti-Federalists
and recognized the necessity of a Bill of Rights. See A True Friend, Broadside:
Richmond, December 6, 1787 (reprinted in Young, at 143) (“Let us then
insert in the first page of this constitution, as a preamble to it, a
declaration of our rights, or an enumeration of our prerogatives, as a sovereign
people; that they may never hereafter be unknown, forgotten or contradicted by
our representatives, our delegates, our servants in Congress . . . .”).
2. Federalists say bill of rights not
needed because federal government given no power to infringe fundamental
rights.
One of the
People, Philadelphia Pennsylvania
Gazette, October 17, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 45)
(“The freedom of the press and trials by jury are not infringed on. The Constitution is silent, and with
propriety too, on these and every other subject relative to the internal
government of the states. These are
secured by the different state constitutions. I repeat again, that the Federal
Constitution does not interfere with these matters. Their power is defined and limited by
the 8th section of the first Article of the Constitution, and they have not
power to take away the freedom of the press, nor can they interfere in the
smallest degree with the judiciary of any of the states.”); A Citizen, Carlisle Gazette, October 24, 1787
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 57) (“The consideration of the nature and
object of this general government will also shew you how weak it is to talk of a
bill of rights in it. It is a
government of states; not of individuals.
The constitution of each state has a bill of rights for its own citizens;
and the proposed plan guaranties to every state a republican form of government
for ever. But it would be a novelty
indeed to form a bill of rights for states.”); James Wilson, Pennsylvania
Convention, November 28, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 114) (“[A]
bill of rights is by no means a necessary measure. In a government possessed of enumerated
powers, such a measure would be not only unnecessary, but preposterous and
dangerous.”); Brutus, Alexandria Virginia Journal, December 6, 1787
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 144) (“The powers which the people
delegate to their rulers are completely defined, and if they should assume more
than is there warranted they would soon find that there is a power in the United
States of America paramount to their own, which would bring upon them the just
resentment of an injured people.”); Cassius XI, Boston Massachusetts Gazette, December 25,
1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 179) (“[O]f what use would be a bill
of rights, in the present case? . .
. It can only be to resort to when it is supposed that Congress have infringed
the unalienble rights of the people: but would it not be much easier to resort
to the federal constitution, to see if therein power is given to Congress to
make the law in question? If such
power is not given, the law is in fact a nullity, and the people will not be
bound thereby. For let it be
remembered that such laws, and such only, as are founded on this constitution,
are to be the supreme laws of the land.”); General Charles Pinckney, South
Carolina Convention, January 18, 1788, (excerpt reprinted in Young, at
217) (“The general government has no powers but what are expressly granted to
it; it therefore has no power to take away the liberty of the press. . . . [T]o
have mentioned it in our general Constitution would perhaps furnish an argument,
hereafter, that the general government had a right to exercise powers not
expressly delegated to it. For the
same reason, we had no bill of rights inserted in our Constitution; for, as we
might perhaps have omitted the enumeration of some of our rights, it might
hereafter be said we had delegated to the general government a power to take
away such of our rights as we had not enumerated . . . .”); Aristides [Alexander
Contee Hanson], Remarks on the Proposed
Plan of a Federal Government, Addressed to the Citizens of the United States of
America, and particularly to the People of Maryland, January 31, 1788
(excerpts reprinted in Young, at 239-42) (“[W]hen the compact [the
Constitution] ascertains and defines the power delegated to the federal head,
then cannot this government, without manifest usurpation, exert any power not
expressly, or by necessary implication, conferred by the compact. This doctrine is so obvious and plain,
that I am amazed any good man should deplore the omission of a bill of
rights.”); Alexander White, Winchester Virginia Gazette, February 22, 1788
(excerpts reprinted in Young, at 281) (“There are other things [in the
Pennsylvania Minority’s proposed Declaration of Rights] so clearly out of the
power of Congress, that the bare recital of them is sufficient, I mean the
‘rights of conscience, or religious liberty–the rights of bearing arms for
defence, or for killing game–the liberty of fowling, hunting and fishing–the
right of altering the laws of descents and distribution of the effects of
deceased persons and titles of lands and goods, and the regulation of contracts
in the individual States.’ These
things seem to have been inserted among their objections, merely to induce the
ignorant to believe that Congress would have a power over such objects and to
infer from their being refused a place in the Constitution, their intention to
exercise that power to the oppression of the people. But if they had been admitted as
reservations out of the powers granted to Congress, it would have opened a large
field indeed for legal construction: I know not an object of legislation which
by a parity of reason, might not be fairly determined within the jurisdiction of
Congress.”) (emphasis added).
3. Federalists argue that bill of rights
may imply federal
government has
power to infringe those rights not mentioned.
James Wilson,
Pennsylvania Convention, November 28, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
at 116) (“In all societies, there are many powers and rights, which cannot be
particularly enumerated. A bill of
rights annexed to a constitution is an enumeration of the powers reserved. If we attempt an enumeration, every
thing that is not enumerated is presumed to be given. The consequence is, that an imperfect
enumeration would throw all implied power into the scale of the government; and
the rights of the people would be rendered incomplete.”); Jasper Yeates,
Pennsylvania Convention, November 30, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
at 125-26) (“I agree with those gentlemen who conceive that a bill of rights,
according to the ideas of the opposition, would be accompanied with considerable
difficulty and danger; for, it might be argued at a future day by the persons
then in power–you undertook to enumerate the rights which you meant to reserve,
the pretension which you now make is not comprised in that enumeration, and,
consequently, our jurisdiction is not circumscribed.”); Brutus, Alexandria Virginia Journal, December 6, 1787
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 144) (“[I]t would therefore have been not
only absurd but even dangerous to have inserted a bill of rights; because, if,
in the enumeration of rights and privileges to be reserved, any had been omitted
or forgotten, and the people, at a future period, should assume those so
omitted, the rulers might with propriety dispute their right to exercise them,
as they were not specified in the bill of rights . . .
.”).
4. Federalists argue bill of rights not
needed as Americans, used to freedom, would not allow infringement of
rights.
Letter from
William Pierce to St. George Tucker (September 28, 1787) (reprinted in
Young, at 29 (“I set this down as a truth founded in nature, that a nation
habituated to freedom will never remain quiet under an invasion of its
liberties.”); A Citizen of
Philadelphia [Pelatiah Webster], The Weakness of Brutus Exposed,
November 8, 1787 (reprinted in Young, at 85) (“[S]hould they [Congress]
assume tyrannical powers, and make incroachments on liberty without the consent
of the people, they would soon attone for their temerity, with shame and
disgrace, and probably with their heads.”); The State Soldier, Richmond Virginia Independent Chronicle,
January 16, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 209) (“[T]here is
nothing in this constitution itself that particularly bargains for a surrender
of your liberties, it must be your own faults if you become enslaved. Men in power may usurp authorities under
any constitution–and those they govern may oppose their tyranny.”); Marcus,
Norfolk and Portsmouth Journal,
March 12, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 297-98) (“It is in the
power of the Parliament if they dare to exercise it, to abolish the trial by
jury altogether–but woe be to the man who should dare to attempt it–it would
undoubtedly produce an insurrection that would hurl every tyrant to the ground
who attempted to destroy that great and just favorite of the English
nation. We certainly shall be
always sure of this guard at least, upon any such act of folly or insanity in
our Representatives: They soon would be taught the consequence of sporting with
the feelings of a free people.”); Publius [Alexander Hamilton], The
Federalist, No. 8, The New York
Packet, November 20, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 105-06)
(footnote omitted) (“The smallness of the army renders the natural strength of
the community an overmatch for it; and the citizens, not habituated to look up
to the military power for [protection], or to submit to its oppressions, neither
love nor fear the soldiery: They view them with a spirit of jealous acquiescence
in a necessary evil, and stand ready to resist a power which they suppose may be
exerted to the prejudice of their rights.
The army under such circumstances, may usefully aid the magistrate to
suppress a small faction, or an occasional mob, or insurrection; but it will be
unable to enforce encroachments against the united efforts of the great body of
the people.”)
5. Federalists argue that federal power to
maintain a standing army should not be feared because the American people are
armed and hence could resist an oppressive standing army.
A
Citizen of America [Federalist Noah
Webster], An Examination into the
Leading Principles of the Federal Constitution (October 10, 1787)
(reprinted in Young, at 40) (“Before a standing army can rule, the people
must be disarmed; as they are in almost every kingdom in Europe. The supreme power in America cannot
enforce unjust laws by the sword; because the whole body of the people are
armed, and constitute a force superior to any band of regular troops that can
be, on any pretense, raised in the United States.”); Essay on Federal
Sentiments, Philadelphia Independent
Gazetteer, October 23, 1787 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 57)
(“If the president and the whole senate should happen to be the boldest
wealthiest, most artful men in the union, supported by the most powerful
connexions, and unanimous in the design of subduing the nation; and if by the
concurrence of the representatives they obtained money and troops for the
purpose; yet the whole personal influence of Congress, and their parricide army
could never prevail over an hundred thousand men armed and disciplined, owners
of the country, animated not only with a spirit of liberty, but ardent
resentment against base treacherous tyrants.”); Mr. Sedgwick, Massachusetts
Convention, January 24, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at 230-31) (“It
was, he said, a chimerical idea to suppose that a country like this could ever
be enslaved. How is an army for
that purpose to be obtained from the freemen of the United States? They certainly, said he, will know to
what object it is to be applied. Is
it possible, he asked, that an army could be raised for the purpose of enslaving
themselves and their brethren? [O]r
if raised, whether they could subdue a nation of freemen, who know how to prize
liberty, and who have arms in their hands?”); Aristides [Alexander Contee
Hanson], Remarks on the Proposed Plan of
a Federal Government, Addressed to the Citizens of the United States of America,
and particularly to the People of Maryland, January 31, 1788 (excerpt
reprinted in Young, at 240) (“If indeed it be possible in the nature of
things, that congress shall, at any future period, alarm us by an improper
augmentation of troops, could we not, in that case, depend on the militia, which
is ourselves.”); A Pennsylvanian III [Tench Coxe], Philadelphia Pennsylvania Gazette, February 20, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 275-76) (“The power of the sword, say the
minority of Pennsylvania is in the hands of Congress. My friends and countrymen, it is not so,
for THE POWERS OF THE SWORD ARE IN THE HANDS OF THE YEOMANRY OF AMERICA FROM
SIXTEEN TO SIXTY. The militia of
these free commonwealths, entitled and accustomed to their arms, when compared
to any possible army must be tremendous and irresistable. Who are these militia? [A]re they not our selves. Is it feared, then, that we shall turn
our arms each man against his own bosom. Congress have no power to disarm the
militia. Their swords, and every
other terrible implement of the soldier, are the birthright of an
American. What clause in the
state or foedral constitution hath given away that important right. . . .
I do not hesitate to affirm, that the unlimited power of the sword is not in the
hands of either the foedral or state governments, but, where I trust in
God it will ever remain, in the hands of the people.”); Foreign
Spectator, REMARKS on the Amendments to the federal Constitution, proposed by
the Conventions of Massachusetts, New-Hampshire, New-York, Virginia, South and
North-Carolina, with the minorities of Pennsylvania and Maryland, by a
FOREIGN SPECTATOR, Number VI, Philadelphia Federal Gazette, November 7, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young, at
556) (“We proceed to consider the amendments that regard the military power of
the federal government. . . . While
the people have property, arms in their hands, and only a spark of a noble
spirit, the most corrupt congress must be mad to form any project of tyranny.”);
The Republican, Hartford Connecticut
Courant, January 7, 1788
(excerpts reprinted in Young, at 188-91) (“it is a capital circumstance
in favor of our liberty that the people themselves are the military power of our
country. In countries under
arbitrary government, the people oppressed and dispirited neither possess arms
nor know how to use them. Tyrants
never feel secure until they have disarmed the people. They can rely upon nothing but standing
armies of mercenary troops for the support of their power. But the people of this country have arms
in their hands; they are not destitute of military knowledge; every citizen is
required by law to be a soldier; we are all marshaled into companies, regiments,
and brigades, for the defense of our country. This is a circumstance which increases
the power and consequence of the people; and enables them to defend their rights
and privileges against every invader. . . . The spirit of the people would
oppose every open and direct attempt to enslave them.”).
Madison expresses
largely the same thought in Federalist No. 46, as follows: “Extravagant as the supposition is, let
it, however, be made. Let a regular
army, fully equal to the resources of the country, be formed; and let it be
entirely at the devotion of the federal government; still it would not be going
too far to say that the State governments with the people on their side would be
able to repel the danger. The
highest number to which, according to the best computation, a standing army can
be carried in any country does not exceed one hundredth part of the whole number
of souls; or one twenty-fifth part of the number able to bear arms. This proportion would not yield, in the
United States, and army of more than twenty-five or thirty thousand men. To these would be opposed a militia
amounting to near half a million citizens with arms in their hands,
officered by men chosen from among themselves, fighting for their common
liberties and united and conducted by governments possessing their affections
and confidence. It may well be
doubted, whether a militia thus circumstanced could ever be conquered by such a
proportion of regular troops. Those
who are best acquainted with the last successful resistance of this country
against the British arms will be most inclined to deny the possibility of
it. Besides the advantage of
being armed, which the Americans possess over the people of almost every other
nation, the existence of subordinate governments, to which the people are
attached and by which the militia officers are appointed, forms a barrier
against the enterprises of ambition, more insurmountable than any which a simple
government of any form can admit of.
Notwithstanding the military establishments in the several kingdoms of
Europe, which are carried as far as the public resources will bear, the
governments are afraid to trust the people with arms. . . . Let us not
insult the free and gallant citizens of America with the suspicion, that they
would be less able to defend the rights of which they would be in actual
possession, than the debased subjects of arbitrary power [Europeans] would be to
rescue theirs from the hands of their oppressors.” (The Federalist Papers, Rossiter,
New American Library, at 299-300; emphasis added.)
6. Federalist argue that federal militia
powers obviated the need for and minimized the likelihood of their being a large
standing army.
In
Federalist No. 29 Hamilton states:
“If a
well-regulated militia be the most natural defense of a free country, it ought
certainly to be under the regulation and at the disposal of that body which is
constituted the guardian of national security. If standing armies are dangerous to
liberty, an efficacious power over the militia in the same body ought, as far as
possible, to take away the inducement and the pretext to such unfriendly
institutions. If the federal
government can command the aid of the militia in those emergencies which call
for the military arm in support of the civil magistrate, it can better dispense
with the employment of a different kind of force. If it cannot avail itself of the former,
it will be obliged to recur to the latter.
To render an army unnecessary will be a more certain method of preventing
its existence than a thousand prohibitions upon paper.” (The Federalist Papers, Rossiter,
New American Library, at 183).
See also James Madison, Virginia Convention, June 14, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, at 400, 402, 404): “If insurrections should arise, or
invasions should take place, the people ought unquestionably to be employed, to
suppress and repel them, rather than a standing army. The best way to do these things was to
put the militia on a good and sure footing, and enable the government to make
use of their services when necessary. . . . [After a response by George
Mason] The most effectual way to
guard against a standing army, is to render it unnecessary. The most effectual way to render it
unnecessary, is to give the general government full power to call forth the
militia, and exert the whole natural strength of the Union, when necessary. . .
. If you limit their [the federal government’s] power over the militia, you give
them a pretext for substituting a standing army.”
ROBERT M. PARKER,
Circuit Judge, specially concurring:
I concur in the
opinion except for Section V. I
choose not to join Section V, which concludes that the right to keep and bear
arms under the Second Amendment is an individual right, because it is dicta and
is therefore not binding on us or on any other court. The determination whether the rights
bestowed by the Second Amendment are collective or individual is entirely
unnecessary to resolve this case and has no bearing on the judgment we dictate
by this opinion. The fact that the
84 pages of dicta contained in Section V are interesting, scholarly, and well
written does not change the fact that they are dicta and amount to at best an
advisory treatise on this long-running debate.
As federal judges
it is our special charge to avoid constitutional questions when the outcome of
the case does not turn on how we answer.
See Spector Motor Service, Inc. v. McLaughlin, 323 U.S. 101, 105
(1944)(“If there is one doctrine more deeply rooted than any other in the
process of constitutional adjudication, it is that we ought not to pass on
questions of constitutionality . . . unless such adjudication is unavoidable.”);
Walton v. Alexander, 20 F.3d 1350, 1356 (5th Cir. 1994)(Garwood, J.,
concurring specially)(“It is settled that courts have a strong duty to avoid
constitutional issues that need not be resolved in order to determine the rights
of the parties to the case under consideration.”)(internal quotations
omitted). Following this cardinal
rule, we will not, for example, pick and choose among dueling constitutional
theories when under any construction the challenged provision is invalid. See Hooper v. Bernalillo County
Assessor, 472 U.S. 612, 621 n.11 (1985). Nor will we decide a constitutional
question when under any construction the challenged provision must be
sustained. See O’Connor v.
Nevada, 27 F.3d 357, 361 (9th Cir. 1994); Bullock v. Minnesota, 611
F.2d 258, 260 (8th Cir. 1979).
Furthermore, the fact that a trial court passed on a novel question of
constitutional law does not require us to do likewise. Appellate courts are supposed to review
judgments, not opinions. See
Texas v. Hopwood, 518 U.S. 1033, 1033 (1996). Here, whether “the district court erred
in adopting an individual rights or standard model as the basis for its
construction of the Second Amendment,” Maj. Op. at 23, is not a question that
affects the outcome of this case no matter how it is answered. In holding that § 922(g)(8) is not
infirm as to Emerson, and at the same time finding an individual right to
gunownership, the majority today departs from these sound precepts of judicial
restraint.
No doubt the
special interests and academics on both sides of this debate will take great
interest in the fact that at long last some court has determined (albeit in
dicta) that the Second Amendment bestows an individual right. The real issue, however, is the fact
that whatever the nature or parameters of the Second Amendment right, be it
collective or individual, it is a right subject to reasonable regulation. The debate, therefore, over the nature
of the right is misplaced. In the
final analysis, whether the right to keep and bear arms is collective or
individual is of no legal consequence.
It is, as duly noted by the majority opinion, a right subject to
reasonable regulation. If
determining that Emerson had an individual Second Amendment right that could
have been successfully asserted as a defense against the charge of violating §
922(g)(8), then the issue would be cloaked with legal significance. As it stands, it makes no
difference. Section 922(g)(8) is
simply another example of a reasonable restriction on whatever right is
contained in the Second Amendment.
And whatever the
scope of the claimed Second Amendment right, no responsible individual or
organization would suggest that it would protect Emerson’s possession of the
other guns found in his military-style arsenal the day the federal indictment
was handed down. In addition to the
Beretta nine millimeter pistol at issue here, Emerson had a second Beretta like
the first, a semi-automatic M-1 carbine, an SKS assault rifle with bayonet, and
a semi-automatic M-14 assault rifle.
Nor would anyone suggest that Emerson’s claimed right to keep and bear
arms supercedes that of his wife, their daughter, and of others to be free from
bodily harm or threats of harm.
Though I see no mention of it in the majority’s opinion, the evidence
shows that Emerson pointed the Beretta at his wife and daughter when the two
went to his office to retrieve an insurance payment. When his wife moved to retrieve her
shoes, Emerson cocked the hammer and made ready to fire. Emerson’s instability and threatening
conduct also manifested itself in comments to his office staff and the
police. Emerson told an employee
that he had an AK-47 and in the same breath that he planned to pay a visit to
his wife’s boyfriend. To a police
officer he said that if any of his wife’s friends were to set foot on his
property they would “be found dead in the parking
lot.”
If the majority
was only filling the Federal Reporter with page after page of non-binding
dicta there would be no need for me to write separately. As I have said, nothing in this case
turns on the original meaning of the Second Amendment, so no court need follow
what the majority has said in that regard.
Unfortunately, however, the majority’s exposition pertains to one of the
most hotly-contested issues of the day.
By overreaching in the area of Second Amendment law, the majority stirs
this controversy without necessity when prudence and respect for stare
decisis calls for it to say nothing at all. See Cass R. Sunstein, One Case at a Time: Judicial
Minimalism and the Supreme Court 5 (1999)(“[A] minimalist path
usually--not always, but usually--makes a good deal of sense when the Court
is dealing with a constitutional issue of high complexity about which many
people feel deeply and on which the nation is divided (on moral or other
grounds).”) (italics in original).
Indeed, in the end, the majority today may have done more harm than good
for those who embrace a right to gunownership.
[1]The district court’s
opinion observes that “[d]uring the [September 4, 1998] hearing, Mrs. Emerson
alleged that her husband threatened over the telephone to kill the man with whom
Mrs. Emerson had been having an adulterous affair.” United States v. Emerson, 46
F.Supp.2d 598, 599 (N.D. Tex. 1999).
[2]On August 28, 1998, the
day Sacha’s petition was filed, Judge Sutton had issued an ex-parte temporary
restraining order prohibiting Emerson from engaging in any of the 29 acts
enumerated in Sacha’s petition pending a hearing on Sacha’s request for a
temporary injunction. These acts
included all those quoted in the text above which the September 14, 1998 order
enjoined Emerson from committing.
The August 28, 1998 order stated that, after examining the petition, the
court “finds that . . . unless [r]espondent . . . is immediately restrained from
the commission of the acts hereinafter prohibited, [r]espondent will commit such
acts before notice of the hearing on temporary injunction can be served and a
hearing had.” This August 28, 1998
order is not the order alleged in the indictment, and in any event it is not
within the terms of § 922(g)(8)(A) which requires that the order have been
“issued after a hearing of which such person received actual notice, and at
which such person had an
opportunity to participate.”
[3]The motion was
apparently made because of problems with a witness. On February 25, 1999, the district court
granted the government’s motion.
[4]The presently relevant
portions of the September 14, 1998, order here cannot be characterized as having
only a transparent or frivolous pretense to
validity.
[5]The reference in this
proposed amendment’s subparagraph (B) to “a person described in subparagraph
(A)” plainly is to the “who is a spouse, former spouse, domestic partner, child,
or former child” language of subparagraph (A).
[6]So far as the record
reflects, this case does not present a situation where the defendant’s firearm
possession is merely incident to (and/or is simply passive pending initiation
and completion of) a good faith effort to rid himself, as soon as after issuance
of the disqualifying court order as reasonably practicable under the
circumstances, of the continued possession of a previously possessed
firearm. Whether such possession is
outside the intended scope of § 922(g)(8), or whether such circumstances
constitute a defense akin to that of necessity, justification or the like, or
whether some such result is constitutionally required (under the Second or Fifth
or Eighth Amendments, or otherwise), is thus not now before us. See, generally, e.g., United States
v. Newcomb, 6 F.3d 1129, 1133-38 (6th Cir. 1993) (preventing harm to
others). Cf. United States v.
Gomez, 81 F.3d 846, 850-54 (9th Cir. 1996) (self-defense); United States
v. Panter, 688 F.2d 268, 269-72 (5th Cir. 1982) (same). We also observe that the charged
possession here was more than 60 days after the September 14, 1998 order. There is no assertion that Emerson did
not know of the order when it was entered or within a day or two
thereafter.
[7]The front of the form
contains a section 8 which consists of 11 separate questions (respectively
labeled “a” through “i”) each of which has an adjoining blank box in which the
purchaser must fill in the answer “yes” or “no.” Question “8j”
asks:
“j. Are you subject to a court order
restraining you from harassing, stalking, or threatening an intimate partner or
child of such partner?” (See important Notice 4 and Definition
4.)”
Emerson, correctly,
filled in the answer “no” to each of questions 8b through
8k.
Just below section 8 of
the form, and just above where Emerson signed the form, is a five line
certificate, all in bold faced and capital letters, which includes the
statement: “I understand that a person who answers ‘yes’ to any of the questions
8b through 8k is prohibited from purchasing or possessing a
firearm.”
The “important Notice 4
and Definition 4" to which question 8j refers the purchaser is set out on the
back of the form as follows:
“4. Under 18 U.S.C. § 922 firearms may not
be sold to or received by persons subject to a court order that: (A) was issued
after a hearing of which the person received actual notice and had an
opportunity to participate; (B) restrains such person from harassing, stalking
or threatening an intimate partner or child of such intimate partner or person,
or engaging in other conduct that would place an intimate partner in reasonable
fear of bodily injury to the partner or child; and (C)(i) includes a finding
that such person represents a credible threat to the physical safety of such
intimate partner or child, or (ii) by its terms explicitly prohibits the use,
attempted use, or threatened use of physical force against such intimate partner
or child that would reasonably be expected to cause bodily
injury.”
We also note that
paragraph (8) of § 922(g) became law in September 1994, P.L. 103-322, Sec.
110401(c), 108 Stat. 1796, 2014-2015, 2151, approximately three years prior to
Emerson’s acquisition of the firearm in question and approximately four years
prior to the September 14, 1998 order.
[8]Emerson assumed, for
purposes of his pretrial motion to dismiss on Commerce Clause grounds, that the
pistol had traveled into Texas in interstate or foreign commerce at some time
prior to his October 10, 1997, purchase of it in Texas. The government likewise so assumed. Neither party alleged, the record does
not reflect, and the district court made no finding as to, when such travel in
interstate or foreign commerce occurred.
Emerson did not contend
below, and does not contend on appeal, that the pistol had not traveled in
interstate or foreign commerce after the 1994 enactment of the current
version of § 922(g)(8). We also
note that Emerson’s 1997 purchase of the pistol was apparently from a federally
licensed firearms leader, although any possible relevance of that to the issue
of congressional Commerce Clause power has not been raised by either party here
or below. See United States v.
Lopez, 2 F.3d 1342, 1348 & n.9 (5th Cir. 1993), affirmed, 115
S.Ct. 1624 (1995). Emerson’s
Commerce Clause challenge as presented below and on appeal, and the government’s
and the district court’s response thereto, does not address either of those
matters, and we do not address either of them. Emerson has not demonstrated error in
the district court’s denial of his pretrial motion to dismiss under the Commerce
Clause.
Even assuming, as we
do, that the instant firearm traveled in interstate commerce after the September
1994 enactment of § 922(g)(8), and though we are bound by our prior precedent,
it nevertheless appears to us that the founding generation would have regarded
as clearly illegitimate any construction of the Commerce Clause which allowed
federal prohibition of mere passive, non-commercial, personal possession of a
firearm acquired in accordance with federal (as well as state) law which
thereafter always remained within the state in which it was
acquired.
[9]See Michael A. Bellesiles,
The Second Amendment in Action, 76 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 61 (2000); Carl T.
Bogus, The History and Politics of Second Amendment Scholarship: A
Primer, 76 Chi.-Kent L. Rev.
3 (2000); Carl T. Bogus, The Hidden History of the Second Amendment, 31
U.C. Davis L.Rev. 309 (1998);
Keith A. Ehrman & Dennis A. Henigan, The Second Amendment in the
Twentieth Century: Have You Seen Your Militia Lately?, 15 U. Dayton L. Rev. 5 (1989); Paul
Finkelman, “A Well Regulated Militia”: The Second Amendment in Historical
Perspective, 76 Chi.-Kent L.
Rev. 195 (2000); Steven J. Heyman, Natural Rights and the Second
Amendment, 76 Chi.-Kent L.
Rev. 237 (2000); H. Richard Uviller & William G. Merkel, The
Second Amendment in Context: The Case of the Vanishing Predicate, 76 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 403
(2000).
Not every proponent of
this model conceives of it in exactly the same way. For example, Heyman and Uviller argue
that the Second Amendment simply guarantees that the federal government will not
do anything to destroy the militia.
[10]In Love v.
Pepersack, 47 F.3d 120, 122 (4th Cir. 1995), a citizen brought suit under 42
U.S.C. § 1983 against state officials for violating, inter alia, her
Second Amendment rights by denying her application to purchase a handgun. After stating that “[t]he Second
Amendment does not apply to the states,” id. at 123, the court goes on to
observe that “the Second Amendment preserves a collective, rather than
individual, right.” Id. at
124.
In United States v.
Warin, 530 F.2d 103, 106 (6th Cir. 1976), also discussed in note 19,
infra, the Sixth Circuit stated: “‘Since the Second Amendment right “to
keep and bear Arms” applies only to the right of the State to maintain a militia
and not to the individual’s right to bear arms, there can be no serious claim to
any express constitutional right of an individual to possess a firearm.’” Id. (quoting Stevens v. United
States, 440 F.2d 144, 149 (6th Cir. 1971)).
In Gillespie v. City
of Indianapolis, 185 F.3d 693 (7th Cir. 1999), a police officer convicted of
a misdemeanor crime of domestic violence was fired because, under 18 U.S.C. §
922(g)(9), he could no longer possess a firearm and was, as a result, unable to
perform his duties. He brought suit
against the city officials and challenged the constitutionality of § 922(g)(9)
on, inter alia, Second Amendment grounds. The Seventh Circuit rejected the
challenge, noting that the Second Amendment’s introductory clause “suggests”
that it “inures not to the individual but to the people collectively, its reach
extending so far as is necessary to protect their common interest in protection
by a militia.” Id. at
710. Despite the collective nature
of the Second Amendment, the court found the plaintiff had standing to mount his
Second Amendment challenge.
Id. at 711. The court
also said that the Second Amendment was not violated because under no “plausible
set of facts” would “the viability and efficacy of state militias . . . be
undermined by prohibiting those convicted of perpetrating domestic violence from
possessing weapons in or affecting interstate commerce.” Id.
Hickman v.
Block,
81 F.3d 98, 99 (9th Cir. 1996), involved another § 1983 suit by a citizen
against state officials who denied his application for a concealed weapons
permit. The Ninth Circuit decided
to “follow our sister circuits in holding that the Second Amendment is a right
held by the states, and does not protect the possession of a weapon by a private
citizen.” Id. at 101. Thus, the plaintiff’s lack of standing
was dispositive, though the court did note that the Second Amendment “is not
incorporated against the states.”
Id. at 103 n.10.
[11]In Cases v. United
States, 131 F.2d 916, 923 (1st Cir. 1942), also discussed in note 19,
infra, the First Circuit concluded that the Second Amendment was not
infringed because there was no evidence that the defendant “was or ever had been
a member of any military organization or that his use of the weapon . . . was in
preparation for a military career” and the evidence showed he was “on a frolic
of his own and without any thought or intention of contributing to the
efficiency of the well regulated militia.”
Id. While the First
Circuit did not explicitly adopt the sophisticated collective rights model, its
analysis is in many respects consonant with it.
In United States v.
Rybar, 103 F.3d 273, 286 (3d Cir. 1996), the Third Circuit held that Rybar’s
membership in the general, unorganized militia established by 10 U.S.C. § 311(a)
did not cause his possession of a machine gun to be so connected with militia
activity that the Second Amendment applied. While Rybar was not clear about
whether it was adopting the states’ rights view or the sophisticated collective
rights view, it seems more consistent with the latter.
In United States v.
Hale, 978 F.2d 1016 (8th Cir. 1992), the Eighth Circuit found it unnecessary
to commit to either the states’ rights or the sophisticated collective rights
model of the Second Amendment. The
court proclaimed that “[c]onsidering this history, we cannot conclude that the
Second Amendment protects the individual possession of military weapons.” Id. at 1019. Yet, the court went on to consider
whether the defendant’s actual possession of machine guns was “reasonably
related to the preservation of a well regulated militia.” Id. at 1020. Like the Third Circuit in Rybar,
the Eighth Circuit held that membership in an unorganized militia did not
satisfy the reasonable relationship test.
The court felt that unless the reasonable relationship test was
satisfied, it was “irrelevant” whether the Second Amendment was collective or
individual in nature.
Id. However, the
court’s inquiry into the nature of the defendant’s possession of the machine
guns is more compatible with the sophisticated collective rights
model.
United States v.
Oakes,
564 F.2d 384 (10th Cir. 1977), is similar to Rybar. In Oakes the Tenth Circuit first
rebuffed the individual rights view of the Second Amendment, then rejected
defendant’s argument that, because he was “technically” a member of the Kansas
militia, as Kansas law defined its militia to include all able-bodied male
citizens between ages 21 and 45, his possession of a machine gun preserved the
effectiveness of the militia such that the Second Amendment applied. The court did not specify whether the
Second Amendment was an individual right of extremely limited scope or whether
it protected only states rather than individuals; however, the court’s
willingness to address the defendant’s state militia argument is more in accord
with the sophisticated collective rights model.
United States v.
Wright, 117 F.3d 1265 (11th
Cir. 1997), is similar to, and relied upon, Hale. The court held that the defendant’s
membership in Georgia’s “unorganized militia”(defined as all able-bodied males
between ages 17 and 45 not in the organized or retired militia–or national
guard–or on the reserve list) did not render his possession of machine guns and
pipe bombs so related to the preservation of a well regulated militia that it
was necessary to determine whether the Second Amendment “creates” a collective
or individual right. Id. at
1273-74 & n.18. The court also
stated that “[t]he possibility that in responding to a future crisis state
authorities might seek the aid of members of the unorganized militia does not
speak to the militia’s current state of regulation.” Again, this approach is consistent with
the sophisticated states’ rights model.
For further discussion
of the sophisticated collective rights model, see Robert J. Cottrol &
Raymond T. Diamond, The Fifth Auxiliary Right, 104 Yale L. J. 995, 1003-1004 (1995) and
Nelson Lund, The Ends of Second Amendment Jurisprudence: Firearms
Disabilities and Domestic Violence Restraining Orders, 4 Tex. Rev. L. & Pol. 157, 184-86
(1999).
[12]See Scott Bursor,
Toward a Functional Framework for Interpreting the Second Amendment, 74
Texas L. Rev. 1125 (1996); Robert
J. Cottrol & Raymond T. Diamond, The Fifth Auxiliary Right, 104 Yale L. J. 995 (1995); Robert Dowlut,
The Right to Arms: Does the Constitution or the Predilection of Judges
Reign?, 36 Okla. L. Rev. 65
(1983); Stephen P. Halbrook, The Right of the People or the Power of the
State: Bearing Arms, Arming Militias, and the Second Amendment, 26 Val. U. L. Rev. 131 (1991); Stephen
P. Halbrook, What the Framers Intended: A Linguistic Analysis of the Right to
“Bear Arms”, 49 Law & Contemp.
Probs. 151 (1986); Don B. Kates, Jr., The Second Amendment and the
Ideology of Self-Protection, 9
Const. Comm. 87 (1992); Don
B. Kates, Jr., Handgun Prohibition and the Original Meaning of the Second
Amendment, 82 Mich. L. Rev.
204 (1983); Sanford Levinson, The Embarrassing Second Amendment, 99 Yale L. J. 637 (1989); Nelson Lund,
The Ends of Second Amendment Jurisprudence: Firearms Disabilities and
Domestic Violence Restraining Orders, 4 Tex. Rev. L. & Pol. 157 (1999);
Nelson Lund, The Past and Future of the Individual’s Right to Arms, 31 Ga. L. Rev. 1 (1996); Glenn H.
Reynolds, A Critical Guide to the Second Amendment, 62 Tenn. L. Rev. 461 (1995); Robert E.
Shalhope, The Ideological Origins of the Second Amendment, 69 J. Am. Hist. 599 (1982); William Van
Alstyne, The Second Amendment and the Personal Right to Arms, 43 Duke L. J. 1236 (1994); Eugene Volokh,
The Commonplace Second Amendment, 73 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 793
(1998).
[13]In United States v.
Cruikshank, 23 L.Ed. 588 (1875), the Court held that the Second Amendment
“is one of the amendments that has no other effect than to restrict the powers
of the National Government.”
Id. at 592. In
Presser v. Illinois, 6 S.Ct. 580, 584 (1886), the Court, reaffirming
Cruikshank and citing Barron v. Baltimore, 8 L.Ed. 672 (1833),
held that the Second “amendment is a limitation only upon the power of congress
and the national government, and not upon that of the state.” And, in Miller v. Texas, 14 S.Ct.
874 (1894), the Court held, with respect to “the second and fourth amendments”
that “the restrictions of these amendments operate only upon the federal power,
and have no reference whatever to proceedings in state courts,” citing Barron
v. Baltimore and Cruikshank.
As these holdings all came well before the Supreme Court began the
process of incorporating certain provisions of the first eight amendments into
the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, and as they ultimately rest
on a rationale equally applicable to all those amendments, none of them
establishes any principle governing any of the issues now before us.
[14]The Court’s opinion
quotes the entire indictment, id. at 816, and likewise quotes all the
relevant provisions of the National Firearms Act (then codified at 26 U.S.C. §§
1132 et seq.), including the definition (in its section 1) of a “firearm” as
including “a shotgun or rifle having a barrel of less than eighteen inches in
length.” Id.
n.1.
[15]The demurrer further
urged that the National Firearms Act was also unconstitutional because it was
“not a revenue measure but an attempt to usurp police power reserved to the
States.” Miller at 817. The district court did not address this
contention. The Supreme Court
dismissed it as “plainly untenable,” citing Sonzinksky v. United States,
57 S.Ct. 554 (1937), and several cases “under the Harrison Narcotic Act,”
including Nigro v. United States, 48 S.Ct. 388 (1927). Miller at 818. The government’s brief addressed only
the issue of whether section 11 of the National Firearms Act contravened the
Second Amendment.
[16]The government’s
Miller brief (pp. 12-14) also quotes at length from Aymette at pp.
156-57 as background support for its first argument (namely that the
Second Amendment protects arms bearing only where it occurs during actual
militia service). However, while
some of the Aymette language quoted tends in that direction, the actual
holding of that case appears to rest on the basis stated in the quotation set
out in the text above. In
Aymette the defendant appealed his conviction of violating the statute
making it a misdemeanor to “wear any bowie knife . . . under his clothes, or . .
. concealed about his person.” The
evidence showed that the defendant, with “a bowie-knife concealed under his
vest,” went into a hotel looking for an individual he said he intended to
kill. He contended on appeal that
the conviction violated the provision of the Tennessee constitution declaring
“that the free white men of this State have a right to keep and bear arms for
their common defence.” The court
emphasized the presence and significance of the word “common.” But although it was obvious from the
facts recited that the defendant was not engaged in any character of militia
service on the occasion in question, but was rather engaged only in an entirely
personal activity of his own, the Aymette court did not make this a
ground for its decision. Rather, it
appears to have affirmed on the basis that [t]he Legislature . . . have a right
to prohibit the wearing or keeping weapons . . . which are not usual in
civilized warfare, or would not contribute to the common defence” and,
alternatively, that “the Legislature may prohibit such manner of wearing [arms]
as would never be resorted to by persons engaged in the common defence.” Id. at
159.
[17]In Robertson the
Court, in upholding the constitutionality of the federal statute authorizing the
apprehension, imprisonment and return of deserting merchant seamen, stated, in
the passage obviously referred to in the government’s Miller brief, as
follows (17 S.Ct. at 329):
“. . . the first 10
amendments to the constitution, commonly known as the ‘Bill of Rights,’ were not
intended to lay down any novel principles of government, but simply to embody
certain guaranties and immunities which we had inherited from our English
ancestors, and which had, from time immemorial, been subject to certain
well-recognized exceptions, arising from the necessities of the case. In incorporating these principles into
the fundamental law, there was no intention of disregarding the exceptions,
which continued to be recognized as if they had been formally expressed. Thus, the freedom of speech
and of the press (article 1) does not permit the publication of libels,
blasphemous or indecent articles, or other publications injurious to public
morals or private reputation; the right of the people to keep and bear arms
(article 2) is not infringed by laws prohibiting the carrying of concealed
weapons; the provision that no person shall be twice put in jeopardy
(article 5) does not prevent a second trial, if upon the first trial the
jury failed to agree, or if the verdict was set aside upon the defendant’s
motion . . . nor does the provision of the same article that no one shall be
a witness against himself impair his obligation to testify, if a prosecution
against him be barred by the lapse of time, a pardon, or by statutory enactment
. . . Nor does the provision that an accused person shall be confronted with
the witnesses against him prevent the admission of dying declarations, or
the depositions of witnesses who have died since the former trial.” (emphasis
added)
The Miller
opinion cites Robertson.
Miller, 59 S.Ct. at 820 n.3.
[18]We also observe that
the Miller opinion’s above reference in quotation marks to a shotgun
“‘having a barrel of less than eighteen inches in length’” is a quotation from
section 1 of the National Firearms Act, not from the indictment (which refers to
“a double barrel 12-gauge Stevens shotgun having a barrel less than 18 inches in
length”).
[19]We note that Justice
Thomas, in his concurring opinion in Printz v. United States, 117 S.Ct.
2365, 2386 n.1 (1997), remarked that “[i]n Miller, we determined that the
Second Amendment did not guarantee a citizen’s right to possess a sawed-off
shotgun because that weapon had not been shown to be ‘ordinary military
equipment’ that could ‘contribute to the common defense.’ The Court did not, however, attempt to
define, or otherwise construe, the substantive right protected by the Second
Amendment.”
Further, in Cases v.
United States, 131 F.2d 916, 922 (1st Cir. 1942), the First Circuit
interpreted Miller as resting entirely on the type of weapon involved not having any
reasonable relationship to preservation or efficiency of a well regulated
militia. The Cases court,
however, stated that “we do not feel that the Supreme Court in this case
[Miller] was attempting to formulate a general rule applicable to all
cases. The rule which it laid down
was adequate to dispose of the case before it and that we think was as far as
the Supreme Court intended to go.”
Id., 131 F.2d at 922. Cases thereafter
observes:
“Considering the many
variable factors bearing upon the question it seems to us impossible to
formulate any general test by which to determine the limits imposed by the
Second Amendment but that each case under it, like cases under the due process
clause, must be decided on its own facts and the line between what is and what
is not a valid federal restriction pricked out by decided cases falling on one
side or the other of the line.”
Id.
Cases then goes on, without
further analysis or citation of authority,
to conclude that although the weapon there involved (a .38 caliber
revolver) “may be capable of military use, or . . . familiarity with it . . . of
value in training a person to use a comparable weapon of military type,”
nevertheless the Second Amendment was not infringed because “there is no
evidence that the appellant was or ever had been a member of any military
organization or that his use of the weapon . . . was in preparation for a
military career” but he was rather “simply on a frolic of his own and without
any thought or intention of contributing to the efficiency of the well regulated
militia which the Second Amendment was designed to foster . . . .” Id. at
922-23.
In United States v.
Warin, 530 F.2d 103 (6th Cir. 1976), the court (rejecting a Second Amendment
challenge to a conviction for possessing an unregistered 7 ˝ inch barrel
submachine gun contrary to the National Firearms Act), though concluding that
“‘the Second Amendment right’ ‘to keep and bear arms’ applies only to the right
of the State to maintain a militia and not to the individual’s right to bear
arms,’” nevertheless recognized that this conclusion was not based on
Miller, stating that Miller “did not reach the question of the
extent to which a weapon which is ‘part of the ordinary military equipment’ or
whose ‘use could contribute to the common defense’ may be regulated” and
agreeing with Cases “that the Supreme Court did not lay down a general
rule in Miller.” Id.,
530 F.2d at 105-06. The court also
stated that the Second Amendment, even if it protected individual rights, “does
not constitute an absolute barrier to the congressional regulation of firearms,”
noting that “even the First Amendment has never been treated as establishing an
absolute prohibition against limitations on the rights guaranteed therein.” Id. at
107.
[20]Article 1, § 8
commences “The Congress shall have Power,” and states in clauses 15 and
16:
“To provide for calling
forth the Militia to execute the Laws of the Union, suppress Insurrections and
repel Invasions;
To provide for
organizing, arming, and disciplining, the Militia, and for governing such Part
of them as may be employed in the Service of the United States, reserving to the
States respectively, the Appointment of the Officers, and the Authority of
training the Militia according to the discipline prescribed by
Congress;”
[21]The government relies
on language in a footnote in Lewis v. United States, 100 S.Ct. 915, 921
n.8 (1980), stating with respect to the then felon-in-possession statute (former
18 U.S.C. App. § 1202(a)(1)):
“These legislative
restrictions on the use of firearms are neither based upon constitutionally
suspect criteria, nor do they trench upon any constitutionally protected
liberties. See United States v.
Miller, . . ., 59 S.Ct. 816, 818 . . . (1939) (the Second Amendment
guarantees no right to keep and bear a firearm that does not have “some
reasonable relationship to the preservation or efficiency of a well regulated
militia”).”
This does not suggest a
collective rights or sophisticated collective rights approach to the Second
Amendment any more than does Miller itself. We also note that recognition that the
Second Amendment does not prohibit legislation such as former § 1202(a)(1) is in
no way inconsistent with an individual rights model. See, e.g., Robertson v. Baldwin,
17 S.Ct. 326, 329 (1897) (quoted in note 17, supra) (bill of rights
protections are not absolutes but subject to exceptions, so the First Amendment
does not permit the publication of libels, the Second Amendment “is not
infringed by laws prohibiting the carrying of concealed weapons,” the double
jeopardy clause does not preclude retrial where the jury fails to agree, the
confrontation clause does not exclude dying declarations, etc.). See also Robert Dowlut, The
Right to Arms: Does the Constitution or the Predilection of Judges Reign?,
36 Okla
L. Rev. 65, 96 (1983)
(“Colonial and English societies of the eighteenth century, as well as their
modern counterparts, have excluded infants, idiots, lunatics, and felons [from
possessing firearms].”); Stephen P. Halbrook, What the Framers Intended:
A Linguistic Analysis of the Right to “Bear Arms”, 49 Law & Contemp. Probs. 151 (1986) (“violent
criminals, children, and those of unsound mind may be deprived of firearms . . .
.”); Don B. Kates, Jr., Handgun Prohibition and the Original Meaning of the
Second Amendment, 82 Mich. L. Rev. 204, 266 (1983) (“Nor
does it seem that the Founders considered felons within the common law right to
arms or intended to confer any such right upon them.”). We further observe that Lewis
presented no Second Amendment
challenge to the § 1202(a)(1) conviction and the Second Amendment was not
at issue there.
The government also
cites in this connection our decisions in United States v. Williams, 446
F.2d 486 (5th Cir. 1971), and United States v. Johnson, 441 F.2d 1134
(5th Cir. 1971), but these National Firearms Act unregistered sawed-off shotgun
prosecutions do no more than apply Miller to virtually identical facts
and do not adopt or suggest that Miller adopted a collective rights or
sophisticated collective rights approach to the Second
Amendment.
[22]There is no contention
here that the Beretta pistol possessed is a kind or type of weapon that is
neither “any part of the ordinary military equipment” nor such “that its use
could contribute to the common defense” within the language of Miller
(nor that it is otherwise within the kind or type of weapon embraced in the
government’s second Miller argument, e.g., “weapons which can have no
legitimate use in the hands of private individuals” so as to be categorically
excluded from the scope of the Second Amendment under Miller’s
holding).
[23]As noted below in our
discussion of the history of the Second Amendment, many Americans at this time
not only feared a standing army but also a select militia, a militia comprised
of only a relatively few selected individuals (perhaps the youngest and fittest)
who were more frequently and better trained and equipped than the general,
unorganized militia. Such a select
militia would be analogous to today’s National
Guard.
[24]See U.S. Const. Art. I, § 1, Cl. 1 (“[a]ll
legislative Powers herein granted shall be vested in a Congress of the United
States . . . .”); Art 1, § 8, Cl. 16 (“reserving to the States respectively, the
Appointment of the Officers, and the Authority of training the Militia according
to the discipline prescribed by Congress.”); Art. II, § 1, Cl. 1 (“The executive
Power shall be vested in a President of the United States of America.”); Art.
III, § 1, Cl. 1 (“The judicial Power of the United States, shall be vested in
one supreme Court . . . .”); amend.
I (“Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or
prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of
the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to
petition the Government for a redress of grievances.”) (emphasis added); amend.
II (“[a] well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free
State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be
infringed.”) (emphasis added); amend. IV (“The right of the people to be
secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects, against unreasonable
searches and seizures, shall not be violated, and no Warrants shall issue, but
upon probable cause, supported by Oath or affirmation, and particularly
describing the place to be searched, and the persons or things to be seized.”)
(emphasis added); amend. IX (“[t]he enumeration in the Constitution, of certain
rights, shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the
people.”); amend. X (“[t]he powers not delegated to the United States by the
Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States
respectively, or to the people.”).
It is also plain that
the First Congress knew full well how to distinguish between “the people” and
the states, e.g. amend. X.
[25]See U.S. Const. Art. 1, § 8, Cl. 15 (“[t]o
provide for calling forth the Militia to execute the Laws of the Union, suppress
Insurrections and repel Invasions;” amend. V (“No person shall be held to answer
for a capital, or otherwise infamous crime, unless on a presentation or
indictment of a Grand Jury, except in cases arising in the land or naval forces,
or in the Militia, when in actual service in time of War or public danger . . .
.”).
[26]The cited portions of
Casey and Moore quote with approval from Justice Harlan’s
dissenting opinion in Poe v. Ullman, 81 S.Ct. 1752, 1776-77 (1961), the
following passage (among others), viz:
“‘[T]he full scope of
the liberty guaranteed by the Due Process Clause cannot be found in or limited
by the precise terms of the specific guarantees elsewhere provided in the
Constitution. This ‘liberty’ is not
a series of isolated points pricked out in terms of the taking of property; the
freedom of speech, press, and religion; the right to keep and bear arms; the
freedom from unreasonable searches and seizures; and so
on.’”
The same language is
quoted with approval in Justice White’s Moore dissent. Id., 97 S.Ct. at 1957-58. An earlier portion of the Casey
opinion speaks of rejecting the notion that Fourteenth Amendment “liberty
encompasses no more than those rights already guaranteed to the
individual against federal interference by the express provisions of the
first eight Amendments.”
Id. at 2804-05 (emphasis added).
[27]Justice Black’s
concurring opinion in Duncan quotes with approval a portion of the
remarks of Senator Howard on introducing the Fourteenth Amendment for passage in
the Senate, stating that its privileges and immunities clause should
include:
“‘. . . the personal
rights guarantied and secured by the first eight amendments of the
Constitution; such as the freedom of speech and of the press; the right
of the people peaceably to assemble and petition the Government for a redress of
grievances, a right appertaining to each and all the people; the right to
keep and to bear arms; the right to be exempted from the quartering of
soldiers in a house without the consent of the owner; the right to be exempt
from unreasonable searches and seizures, and from any search or seizure except
by virtue of a warrant issued upon a formal oath or affidavit; the right of an
accused person to be informed of the nature of the accusation against him, and
his right to be tried by an impartial jury of the vicinage; and also the right
to be secure against excessive bail and against cruel and unusual punishments.’”
Id. at 1456 (emphasis added).
[28]New Hampshire’s 1784
Constitution contained such a provision and Rhode Island’s 1790 ratification
convention proposed an amendment to the United States Constitution that would
have included a conscientious objector clause.
[29]See Ala. Const. Art. 1, § 23 (1819) (“Every
citizen has a right to bear arms in defense of himself and the state.”); Conn. Const. Art. I, § 17 (1818)
(“Every citizen has a right to bear arms in defense of himself and the State.”);
Ind. Const. Art. I, § 20 (1816)
(“That the people have a right to bear arms for the defence of themselves and
the State; and that the military shall be kept in strict subordination to the
civil power.”); Ky. Const. Art. 10, ¶ 23 (1792) (“That the right of the citizens
to bear arms in defense of themselves and the State, shall not be
questioned”); Mich. Const. Art.
I, § 13 (1835) (“Every person has a right to keep and bear arms for the defense
of himself and the State.”); Miss.
Const. Art. I, § 23 (1817) (“Every citizen has a right to bear arms, in
defence of himself and the State.”); Mo.
Const. Art. XIII, § 3 (1820) (“That the people have the right peaceably
to assemble for their common good,
and to apply to those vested with the powers of government for redress of
grievances by petition or remonstrance; and that their right to bear arms in
defense of themselves and of the State cannot be questioned.”);Ohio Const. Art. VIII, § 20 (1802)
(“That the people have a right to bear arms for the defense of themselves and
the State; and as standing armies, in time of peace, are dangerous to liberty,
they shall not be kept up, and that the military shall be kept under strict
subordination to the civil power.”); Pa.
Const., Declaration of the Rights of the Inhabitants of the Commonwealth
or State of Pennsylvania, Art. XIII (September 28, 1776) (“That the people have
a right to bear arms for the defence of themselves and the state;”); Pa. Const. Art. I, § 21 (1790)
(“The right of the citizens to bear arms in defense of themselves and the State
shall not be questioned.”); Vt.
Declaration of the Rights of the Inhabitants of the State of Vermont Chp.
1 art. XV (July 8, 1777) (“That the people have a right to bear arms for the
defence of themselves and the State”) (note, Vermont was claimed by New York,
and was not recognized as a state until 1791).
[30]We also observe that to
interpret state constitutional provision protecting the right of the citizen or
the people to “bear arms” as applying only where the individual is actively
engaged in actual military service is necessarily to either (1)
contemplate actual military service for that purpose as including military
service other than that which is ordered or directed by the government;
or (2) construe the constitutional provision as saying no more than that
the citizen has a right to do that which the state orders him to do and thus
neither grants the citizen any right nor in any way restricts the power of the
state. Of course, the latter
difficulty is especially applicable to the theory that such state constitutional
provisions grant rights only to the state.
While two (and only two) state courts (both in the twentieth century)
have seemingly adopted that view, those two decisions do not appear to even
recognize, much less attempt to justify, the anomaly of construing a
constitutional declaration of rights as conferring rights only on the state
which had them anyway. See City
of Salina v. Blaksley, 72 Kan. 230, 83 P. 619 (Kan. 1905) (in prosecution
for carrying a pistol within city limits while intoxicated, construing bill of
rights provision “that the people have the right to bear arms for their defense
and security” as one which “refers to the people as a collective body” and which
“deals exclusively with the military.
Individual rights are not considered in this section.”); Commonwealth
v. Davis, 343 N.E.2d 847 (Mass. 1976) (in prosecution for possession of
shotgun with barrel less than 18 inches long, provision of § 17 of bill of
rights that “the people have a right to keep and bear arms for the common
defense” is “not directed to guaranteeing individual ownership or possession of
weapons;” while a “law forbidding the keeping by individuals of arms that were
used in the militia service might then have interfered with the effectiveness of
the militia and thus offended the art. 17 right . . . that situation no longer
exists; our militia, of which the backbone is the National Guard, is now
equipped and supported by public funds.”).
[31]We note that in
Aymette, supra, the Tennessee Supreme Court, in analyzing § 26 of
its bill of rights (“that the free white men of this State have a right to keep
and bear arms for their common defence”), construed differently the “keep” and
the “bear” portions of that section.
As to the “bear” aspect, the court looked to § 28 of the bill of rights
(“no citizen of this State shall be required to bear arms provided he will pay
an equivalent”) and opined that “bear” arms “has a military sense.” It likewise said that in § 26 “the arms
the right to keep which is secured are such as are usually employed in civilized
warfare” not “those weapons which are usually employed in private broils, and
which are efficient only in the hands of the robber and the assassin.” Aymette thereafter observed that
as to “arms” of the type covered by § 26:
“The citizens have
the unqualified right to keep the weapon, it being of the character
before described as being intended by this provision. But the right to bear arms is not of
that unqualified character. The
citizens may bear them for the common defence; but it does not follow that they
may be borne by an individual, merely to terrify the people or for purposes of
private assassination. And, . . .
the Legislature may prohibit such manner of wearing as would never be resorted
to by persons engaged in the common defence.” (emphasis added)
This is consistent with
the Court’s earlier observation respecting § 26 that “although this right must
be inviolably preserved, yet it does not follow that the Legislature is
prohibited altogether from passing laws regulating the manner in which these
arms may be employed.”
(emphasis added). A
“military” connotation is given to “bear” and to some extent to “arms” but
not to “keep.” Beyond such
connection as may arise from the general type of weapon, no character of
military status or activity whatever was required to come within the protected
right to “keep . . . arms;” that right was “unqualified;” thought the “the right
to bear arms is not of that unqualified character.”
[32]It seems clear under
longstanding and generally accepted principles of statutory construction, that,
at least where the preamble and the operative portion of the statute may
reasonably be read consistently with each other, the preamble may not properly
support a reading of the operative portion which would plainly be at odds with
what otherwise would be its clear meaning.
See, e.g., Dwarris, A
General Treatise on Statutes, 268, 269 (Wm. Gould & Sons, 1871)
(footnotes omitted) (“The general purview of a statute is not, however,
necessarily to be restrained by any words introductory to the enacting
clauses. Larger and stronger words
in the enactment part of a statute may extend it beyond the preamble. If the enacting words are plain, and
sufficiently comprehensive to embrace the mischief intended to be prevented,
they shall extend to it, though the preamble does not warrant the construction.
. . . But though the preamble cannot control the enacting part of a statute,
which is expressed in clear and unambiguous terms, yet, if any doubt arise on
the words of the enacting part, the preamble may be resorted to, to explain
it. In truth, it then resolves
itself into a question of intention; or in other words, recourse is had to the
primary rules of interpretation.
For the words being doubtful, the preamble is compared to the rest of the
act, in order to collect the intention of the legislature, whether they meant it
to extend to a case like that under consideration.”); Sedgwick, The Interpretation and Construction of
Statutes and Constitutional Law, 43 (Fred Rothman & Co. 1980)
(reprint of 1874 edition with notes) (“In the modern English cases it is said
that the preamble may be used to ascertain and fix the subject matter to which
the enacting part is to be applied.
So, the purview or body of the act may even be restrained by the
preamble, when no inconsistency or contradiction results. But it is well settled that where the
intention of the Legislature is clearly expressed in the purview, the preamble
shall not restrain it, although it be of much narrower import.”); Joel P.
Bishop, Commentaries on the Written Laws
and Their Interpretation, 49 (Little, Brown, 1882) (footnotes omitted)
(“As showing the inducements to the act, it may have a decisive weight in a
doubtful case. But where the body
of the statute is distinct, it will prevail over a more restricted preamble. . .
. We look to this introductory matter for the general intent of the
legislature,–the reasons and principles upon which the law proceeds. So that, to the extent to which these
can influence the interpretation, the preamble becomes important. . . . In the
words of Ellenborough, C.J.: ‘In a vast number of acts of Parliament, although a
particular mischief is recited in the preamble, yet the legislative provisions
extend far beyond the mischief recited.
And whether the words shall be restrained or not must depend on a fair
exposition of the particular statute in each particular case, and not upon any
universal rule of construction.’”).
We also observe the
various particular provisions of the bill of rights of many early state
constitutions contained introductory justification clauses, usually in the form
of a general statement of political or governmental philosophy. Examples are given in Volokh, Commonplace Second Amendment,
supra n.10, 794-95, 814-21.
One such example is the provision of the New Hampshire Constitution of
1784 (pt. 1, art. XVII) stating: “[i]n criminal prosecutions, the trial of facts
in the vicinity where they happen is so essential to the security of the life,
liberty and estate of the citizen, that no crime or offence ought to be tried in
any other county than that in which it is committed. . . .” It would be absurd to construe this
provision to apply only when a judge agrees with the defendant that trial of the
case in another county would likely jeopardize that particular defendant’s life,
liberty or estate.
[33]See also
Senate
Subcomm. on the Constitution of the Committee on The Judiciary, 97 Cong., 2nd
Sess., The Right to Keep and Bear Arms (Comm. Print 1982):
“In 1623, Virginia forbade its colonists to travel unless they were ‘well armed’
. . . In 1658 it required every householder to have a functioning firearm within
his house.” Id. at 9
(footnote omitted). The Militia Act of 1792,
enacted May 8, 1792, defined the militia as “each and every free able-bodied
white male citizen . . . who is or shall be of age eighteen years, and under the
age of forty-five years . . . .” and required each to “provide himself with a
good musket . . . or with a good rifle. . .” 1 Stat. 271
(1792).
The modern militia
statute, 10 U.S.C. § 311 provides:
“(a) The militia of the
United States consists of all able-bodied males at least 17 years of age and,
except as provided in section 313 of title 32, under 45 years of age who are, or
who have made a declaration of intention to become, citizens of the United
States and of female citizens of the United States who are members of the
National Guard.
(b) The classes of the
militia are–
(1) the organized
militia, which consists of the National Guard and the Naval Militia;
and
(2) the unorganized
militia, which consists of the members of the militia who are not members of the
National Guard or the Naval Militia.”
[34]“That the People have a
Right to keep & to bear Arms; that a well regulated Militia, composed of the
Body of the People, trained to Arms, is the proper natural and safe Defence of a
free State . . . .” Richmond
Antifederal Committee Proposed Bill of Rights, § 17, reprinted in
Young, The Origin of the Second
Amendment (2nd ed. 1995) (Golden Oak Books) (hereafter Young), at
390.
Virginia’s proposed
Bill of Rights included a similar provision: “That the people have a right to
keep and bear arms; that a well-regulated militia, composed of the body of the
people trained to arms, is the proper, natural, and safe defence of a free state
. . . .” 3 Jonathan Elliot, The Debates in the Several State Conventions
on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution 659 (2d ed., 1836). North Carolina proposed a virtually
identical provision, 4 Jonathan Elliot, The Debates in the Several State Conventions
on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution 244 (2d ed., 1836), as also
did New York, New York Convention, July 26, 1788, reprinted in
Young, supra, at 480-88.
[35]“It has been urged that
they [standing armies] are necessary to provide against sudden attacks. Would not a well regulated militia, duly
trained to discipline, afford ample security?” The Impartial Examiner, Virginia Independent Chronicle,
February 27, 1788, excerpt reprinted in Young, supra, at
285.
“A well regulated and
disciplined militia, is at all times a good objection to the introduction of
that bane of all free governments–a standing army.” Governor John Hancock, New York Journal, January 28, 1790,
reprinted in Young, supra, at 731.
[36]See, e.g.,
Debates
In The Convention of the Commonwealth of Virginia, reprinted in 3
J. ELLIOT, debates in the several state
Conventions 425 (3d ed. 1937) (statement of George Mason, June 14, 1788)
(“Who are the militia? They consist
now of the whole people....”); letters
from the federal farmer to the republican 123 (W. Bennett ed. 1978)
(ascribed to Richard Henry Lee) (“[a] militia, when properly formed, are in fact
the people themselves....”); Letter from Tench Coxe to the Pennsylvania Gazette
(Feb. 20, 1778), reprinted in The documentary history of the ratification of
the constitution (Mfm. Supp. 1976) (“Who are these militia? are they not ourselves.”)
(emphasis in original).
[37]Hamilton in Federalist
29 likewise obviously considered the militia as being composed of “the people at
large,” though he did not believe such a force could be made very
effective. He states that
“disciplining all of the militia” would be “futile,” requiring more than “a
month” (obviously per year), and that “[l]ittle more can reasonably be aimed at
with respect to the people at large than to have them properly armed and
equipped; and in order to see that this be not neglected, it will be necessary
to assemble them once or twice in the course of a year.” Hamilton therefore took the position
that “the proper establishment of the militia” also required “the formation of a
select corps of moderate size.” The
Federalist Papers, supra at 184-85.
[38]See Appendix–part
1.
[39]See Patrick Henry,
Virginia Convention, June 5, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
supra 34 at 373) (“Your militia is given up to Congress . . . of what
service would militia be to you, when, most probably, you will not have a single
musket in the state? [F]or, as arms
are to be provided by Congress, they may or may not furnish them.”); Patrick
Henry, Virginia Convention, June 9, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
supra at 381) (“We have not one fourth of the arms that would be
sufficient to defend ourselves. The
power of arming the militia, and the means of purchasing arms, are taken from
the states by the paramount powers of Congress. If Congress will not arm them, they will
not be armed at all.”); George Mason, Virginia Convention, June 14, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
supra at 401) (“Under various pretences, Congress may neglect to provide
for arming and disciplining the militia; and the state governments cannot do it,
for Congress has an exclusive right to arm them . . . . Should the national government wish to
render the militia useless, they may neglect them, and let them perish, in order
to have a pretence of establishing a standing
army.”).
[40]Aristocrotis, The Government of Nature Delineated or An
Exact Picture of the New Federal Constitution [Anti-Federalist satire of
the Federalist position], April 15, 1788 (excerpts reprinted in Young,
supra note 34, at 329-335) (“The second class or inactive militia,
comprehends all the rest of the peasants; viz. the farmers, mechanics,
labourers, etc. which good policy will prompt government to disarm. It would be dangerous to trust such a
rable as this with arms in their hands.”); Letter from George Mason to Thomas
Jefferson (May 26, 1788) (excerpt reprinted in Young, supra at
365-66) (“There are many other things very objectionable in the proposed new
Constitution; particularly the almost unlimited Authority over the Militia of
the several States; whereby, under Colour of regulating, them may disarm, or
render useless the Militia, the more easily to govern by a standing Army; or
they may harass the Militia, by such rigid Regulations, and intollerable
Burdens, as to make the People themselves desire it’s Abolition.”); George
Mason, Virginia Convention, June 14, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, supra at 401) (“There are
various ways of destroying the militia.
A standing army may be perpetually established in their stead. I abominate and detest the idea of a
government, where there is a standing army. The militia may be here destroyed by
that method which has been practised in other parts of the world before; that
is, by rendering them useless–by disarming them.”); William Lenoir, North
Carolina Convention, July 30, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, supra at 496-500) (“When we
consider the great powers of Congress, there is great cause of alarm. They can disarm the militia. If they were armed, they would be a
resource against great oppressions.”).
[41]Patrick Henry, Virginia
Convention, June 5, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note
34, at 374) (“If they [Congress] neglect or refuse to discipline or arm our
militia, they will be useless: the states can do neither–this power being
exclusively given to Congress.”).
[42]See A Number of Letters from the Federal Farmer to
the Republican, Letter III, November 8, 1787 (reprinted in Young,
supra note 34, at 91) (“it is true, the yoemanry of the country possess
the lands, the weight of property, possess arms, and are too strong a body of
men to be openly offended–and, therefore, it is urged [by the Federalists], they
will take care of themselves, that men who shall govern will not dare pay any
disrespect to their opinions. It is
easily perceived, that if they have not their proper negative upon passing laws
in congress, or on the passage of laws relative to taxes and armies, they may in
twenty or thirty years be by means imperceptible to them, totally deprived of
that boasted weight and strength: This may be done in a great measure by
congress, if disposed to do it, by modelling the militia. Should one fifth, or one eighth part of
the men capable of bearing arms, be made a select militia, as has been proposed,
and those the young and ardent part of the community, possessed of but little or
no property, and all the others put upon a plan that will render them of no
importance, the former will answer all the purposes of an army, while the latter
will be defenceless.”). See also
note 58, infra.
[43]Luther Martin,
Baltimore Maryland Journal, March
18, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 301-302)
(“That a system [the Constitution] may enable government wantonly to exercise
power over the militia, to call out an unreasonable number from any particular
state without its permission, and to march them upon, and continue them in,
remote and improper services–that the same system should enable the government
totally to discard, render useless, and even disarm the militia, when it would
remove them out of the way of opposing its ambitious views, is by no means
inconsistent, and is really the case in the proposed constitution . . . . It
[the federal government] has also, by another clause, the powers, by
which only the militia can be organized and armed, and by the
neglect of which they may be rendered utterly useless and insignificant, when it
suits the ambitious purposes of government:–Nor is the suggestion unreasonable .
. . that the government might improperly oppress and harass the militia, the
better to reconcile them to the idea of regular troops, who might relieve them
of the burthen, and to render them less opposed to the measures it might be
disposed to adopt for the purpose of reducing them to that state of
insignificancy and uselessness.”); George Mason, Virginia Convention, June 14,
1788 (excerpt reprinted in
Young, supra at 401,402) (“If they [Congress] ever attempt to harass and
abuse the militia, they may abolish them, and raise a standing army in their
stead. . . . If, at any time, our rulers should have unjust and iniquitous
designs against our liberties, and should wish to establish a standing army, the
first attempt would be to render the service and use of militia odious to the
people themselves–subjecting them to unnecessary severity of discipline in time
of peace, confining them under martial law, and disgusting them so much as to
make them cry out. ‘Give us a standing army!’”).
[44]See A Democratic
Federalist, Philadelphia Pennsylvania
Herald, October 17, 1787 (excerpts reprinted in Young,
supra note 34, at 46) (“[T]he federal rulers are vested with each of the
three essential powers of government–their laws are to be paramount to
the laws of the different states.
What then will there be to oppose their encroachments? Should they ever pretend to tyrannize
over the people, their standing army will silence every popular effort;
it will be theirs to explain the powers which have been granted to them. . . .
[T]he liberty of the people will be no more. . . .” Centinel II, Philadelphia Independent Gazetteer,
October 24, 1787 (excerpts reprinted in Young, supra at 59) (“A
standing army with regular provision of pay and contingencies, would afford a
strong temptation to some ambitious man to step up into the throne, and to seize
absolute power.”); Philadelphienses III, Philadelphia Freeman’s Journal, December 5, 1787
(excerpts reprinted in Young, supra at 139) (“And in respect to
the standing army, it will only be made up of profligate idle ruffians,
whose prowess will chiefly consist of feats of cruelty exercised on their
innocent fellow citizens . . . .”); A Farmer, Exeter, New Hampshire Freeman’s Oracle, January 11, 1788
(excerpts reprinted in Young, supra at 206) (“An army, either in
peace or war, is like the locust and caterpillers of Egypt; they bear down all
before them–and many times, by designing men, have been used as an engine to
destroy the liberties of a people, and reduce them to the most abject slavery. .
. . Organize your militia, arm them well, and under Providence they will be a
sufficient security.”); A Ploughman, Winchester Virginia Gazette, March 19, 1788
(reprinted in Young, supra at 303) (“And in order to rivet the
chains of perpetual slavery upon us, they have made a standing army an essential
part of the Federal Constitution, which the world cannot produce an instance of
a more permanent foundation to erect the fabrik of tyranny upon; . . . to keep a
standing army, gives cause to suspect that the rulers are afraid of the people,
or that they may have a design upon them.
If their designs are oppressive, the army is necessary to compleat the
tyranny; if the army is the strongest force in a State, it must be a military
government, and it is eternally true, that a free government and a standing army
are absolutely incompatible.”).
[45]See Philadelphia Freeman’s Journal, January 16, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 211-13) (“They well
know the impolicy of putting or keeping arms in the hands of a nervous people,
at a distance from the seat of a government, upon whom they mean to exercise the
powers granted in that government. . . . Tyrants have never placed any
confidence on a militia composed of freemen. Experience has taught them that a
standing body of regular forces, whenever they can be completely introduced, are
always efficacious in enforcing their edicts, however arbitrary . . . . There is no instance of any government
being reduced to a confirmed tyranny without military oppression; and the first
policy of tyrants has been to annihilate all other means of national activity
and defence, when they feared opposition, and to rely solely upon standing
troops.”); Luther Martin, Genuine Information IV, Baltimore Maryland Gazette, January 17, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, supra at 221) (“[W]hen a government
wishes to deprive their citizens of freedom, and reduce them to slavery,
it generally makes use of a standing army for that purpose, and leaves
the militia in a situation as contemptible as possible, least they might oppose
its arbitrary designs–That in this system [the Constitution],
we give the general government every provision it could wish for, and even
invite it to subvert the liberties of the States and
their citizens, since we give them the right to encrease and keep
up a standing army as numerous as it would wish, and by placing the
militia under its power, enable it to leave the militia totally
unorganized, undisciplined and even to disarm them; while the
citizens, so far from complaining of this neglect, might even
esteem it a favour in the general government, as thereby they would be freed
from the burthen of military duties, and left to their own private occupations
or pleasures.”); Patrick Henry, Virginia Convention, June 5, 1788 (excerpts
reprinted in Young, supra at 370) (“Have we the means of resisting
disciplined armies, when our only defence, the militia, is put into the hands of
Congress?”).
[46]George Mason, Virginia
Convention, June 14, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 402) (“I
wish that, in case the general government should neglect to arm and discipline
the militia, there should be an express declaration that the state governments
might arm and discipline them.”).
[47]See Appendix–part 2.
[48]See Appendix–part
3.
[49]See Appendix–part
4.
[50]See Appendix–part
5.
[51]See Appendix–part 6.
[52]James Madison, Virginia
Convention, June 14, 1788
(excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 403) (“I
cannot conceive that this Constitution, by giving the general government the
power of arming the militia, takes it away from the state governments. The power is concurrent, and not
exclusive.”); Patrick Henry, Virginia Convention, June 14, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
supra at 407) (“The great object is, that every man be armed. . . . When this power is given up to Congress
without limitation or bounds, how will your militia be armed? You trust to chance; for sure I am that
that nation which shall trust its liberties in other hands cannot long
exist. If gentlemen are serious
when they suppose a concurrent power, where can be the impolicy to amend
it?”).
[53]Some of the
Federalists’ responses, e.g., James Madison’s in Federalist 46, spoke of the
militia as defending the people against federal tyranny. Opponents of the individual rights view
assert that these references to the militia indicate that the Federalists’
response depended not on the people being armed, but on the states having the
power to arm the militia. While it
is true that the Anti-Federalists desired this concession, the Second Amendment
did not provide it. We think
Madison’s message in Federalist 46 is clear: the Anti-Federalists were not to
worry about federal tyranny because those who comprised the militia could
resist such tyranny since the the American people were armed. Federalist 46 speaks about the
significance of the government trusting the people with arms and of the
states as a “barrier against the enterprises of ambition”, but does not
say that the state governments had (or would be given) power to arm the
militia. Federalist 46 clearly
depends, in large part, on the American people being armed. In this respect, Madison’s rationale in
Federalist 46 is substantially the same as that of the Second Amendment which he
would craft over a year later.
[54]This was one of several
clauses which Madison’s proposal, in its fourth (“fourthly”) section, called for
to be inserted in art. 1, § 9, between clauses 3 and 4, the others to be
inserted there all being provisions which eventually became the First, Third,
Fourth, Eighth and Ninth Amendments and portions of the Fifth and Sixth
Amendments.
The other portions of
what became the Fifth and Sixth Amendments, as well as what became the Seventh
Amendment, Madison’s proposal would have as additions to Article 3, § 2.
Madison’s proposal
called for what became the Tenth Amendment to be (together with a separation of
powers provision) in a new Article 7, with existing Article 7 to be renumbered
Article 8.
Madison also proposed
to amend Art. 1, § 2, cl. 3 (number of representatives), Art. 1, § 6, cl. 1
(compensation of representatives), and Art. 1, § 10 (to prohibit states from
denying equal rights of conscience, freedom of the press or jury trial in
criminal cases).
[55]Before the close vote
was taken, Congressman Benson offered another rationale for striking the clause,
and it was he who actually moved to strike. Benson believed there was no natural
right to be exempted from military service and that such exemptions should be
left to the “benevolence” of the legislature. House of Representatives, Debates,
August 17, 1789 (excerpt reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at
697).
[56]If this was what Scott
was thinking, he was wrong. As will
be shown, proposals to limit the federal government’s power to maintain a
standing army were defeated in both the House and the
Senate.
[57]This rejected amendment
read:
“That each state,
respectively, shall have the power to provide for organizing, arming, and
disciplining, its own militia, whensoever Congress shall omit or neglect to
provide for the same; that the militia shall not be subject to martial law,
except when in actual service, in time of war, invasion, or rebellion; and when
not in the actual service of the United States, shall be subject only to such
fines, penalties, and punishments, as shall be directed or inflicted by the laws
of its own state.” Journal of the First Session of the
Senate 75 (Washington, D.C. 1820).
In Houston v.
Moore, 18 U.S. [5 Wheat] 1, 5 L.Ed. 19 (1820), the Supreme Court held that
states retain the power to organize, arm, and discipline their militias provided
that the exercise thereof is not repugnant to the authority of the Union. The Court reasoned that because the
Constitution failed to divest the states of their preexistent militia powers,
such powers remained. Id. 5
L.Ed. at 22-23. The majority did not rely upon or even refer to the Second
Amendment.
The only mention of the
Second Amendment was by Justice Story in his dissent, wherein he observed that
the Second Amendment probably did not have “any important bearing” on the
question of whether states had power to organize, arm, and discipline their
militias. Id. 5 L.Ed. at 31.
It seems likely that if
the Second Amendment was intended only to grant the states concurrent power to
organize, arm, and discipline their militias, the Supreme Court would have
relied, at least in part, upon the Second Amendment for its holding. As it happened, the only mention of the
Second Amendment was by the dissent in pointing out the Second Amendment’s
probable irrelevance to the state militia powers
issue.
[58]See note 42, supra,
and the following: John Smilie,
Pennsylvania Convention, December 6, 1787
(excerpts reprinted in Young, supra note 34, at 145-46) (“I
object to the power of Congress over the militia and to keep a standing army. .
. . Congress may give us a select militia which will, in fact, be a standing
army–or Congress, afraid of a general militia, may say there shall be no militia
at all. When a select militia is
formed, the people in general may be disarmed.”); Centinel IX, Philadelphia
Independent Gazetteer, January 8,
1788 (excerpt reprinted in
Young, supra 192) (footnote omitted) (“I was ever jealous of the select
militia, consisting of infantry and troops of horse, instituted in this city and
some of the counties, . . . . Are not these corps provided to suppress the first
efforts of freedom, and to check the spirit of the people until a regular and
sufficiently powerful military force shall be embodied to rivet the chains of
slavery on a deluded nation.”); A Countryman, New York Journal, January 22, 1788 (excerpt reprinted in Young,
supra at 224) (“Should the new constitution be sufficiently corrected
by a substantial bill of rights . . . separating the legislative,
judicial and executive departments entirely, and confining the national
government to its proper objects; but, by no means admitting a standing army in
time of peace, nor a select militia, which last, is a scheme that a certain head
has, for some time, been teeming with, and is nothing else but an artful
introduction to the other . . . I imagine we might become a happy and
respectable people.”); See An
Additional Number of Letters from the Federal Farmer to the Republican,
Letter XVIII, May 1788 (reprinted in Young, supra at 354-55)
(footnote omitted) (“First, the constitution ought to secure a genuine and guard
against a select militia, by providing that the militia shall always be kept
well organized, armed, and disciplined, and include, according to the past and
general usuage of the states, all men capable of bearing arms; and that all
regulations tending to render this general militia useless and defenceless, by
establishing select corps of militia, or distinct bodies of military men, not
having permanent interests and attachments in the community to be avoided. . . .
But, say gentlemen, the general militia are for the most part employed at home
in their private concerns, cannot well be called out, or be depended upon; that
we must have a select militia; that is, as I understand it, particular corps or
bodies of young men, and of men who have but little to do at home, particularly
armed and disciplined in some measure, at the public expence, and always ready
to take the field. These corps, not
much unlike regular troops, will ever produce an inattention to the general
militia; and the consequence has ever been, and always must be, that the
substantial men, having families and property, will generally be without arms,
without knowing the use of them, and defenceless; whereas, to preserve liberty,
it is essential that the whole body of the people always possess arms, and be
taught alike, especially when young, how to use them; nor does it follow from
this, that all promiscuously must go into actual service on every occasion. The mind that aims at a select militia,
must be influenced by a truly anti-republican principle . . .
.”).
[59]Sent to the states at
the same time were proposed amendments to Art. 1, § 2, cl. 3 (number of
representatives) and Art. 1, § 6, cl. 1 (compensation of representatives). Neither was ratified with the Bill of
Rights, although the latter was (at least arguably) ultimately ratified as the
Twenty-seventh Amendment in May 1992.
[60]While there is no
historical evidence that the states’ rights view of the Second Amendment is
correct, we are struck by the absence of any indication that the result
contemplated by the sophisticated collective rights view was desired, or even
conceived of, by anyone.
[61]The district court’s
analysis of the constitutionality of section 922(g)(8), was essentially as
follows:
“18 U.S.C. §
922(g)(8) is unconstitutional because it allows a state court divorce
proceeding, without particularized findings of the threat of future violence, to
automatically deprive a citizen of his Second Amendment rights. . . . All that
is required for prosecution under the Act is a boilerplate order with no
particularized findings.
Thus, the statute has no real safeguards against an arbitrary abridgement
of Second Amendment rights. Therefore, by criminalizing protected Second
Amendment activity based upon a civil state court order with no particularized
findings, the statute is over-broad and in direct violation of an individual's
Second Amendment rights.
By contrast, §
922(g)(8) is different from the felon-in-possession statute, 18 U.S.C. §
922(g)(1), because once an individual is convicted of a felony, he has by his
criminal conduct taken himself outside the class of law-abiding citizens who
enjoy full exercise of their civil rights. Furthermore, the convicted felon
is admonished in state and federal courts that a felony conviction results in
the loss of certain civil rights, including the right to bear arms. This is not so with § 922(g)(8). .
. . It is absurd that a
boilerplate state court divorce order can collaterally and automatically
extinguish a law-abiding citizen's Second Amendment rights, particularly when
neither the judge issuing the order, nor the parties nor their attorneys are
aware of the federal criminal penalties arising from firearm possession after
entry of the restraining order.”
United States v.
Emerson, 46 F.Supp.2d
598, 610-11 (N.D. Tex. 1999).
[62]Likewise, the Supreme
Court has remarked that the right to keep and bear arms is, like other rights
protected by the Bill of Rights, “subject to certain well-recognized exceptions,
arising from the necessities of the case” and hence “is not infringed by laws
prohibiting the carrying of concealed weapons,” Robertson v. Baldwin, 17
S.Ct. 326, 329 (1897), or by laws “which only forbid bodies of men to associate
together as military organizations . . . to drill or parade in cities and towns
unless authorized by law.”
Presser v. Illinois, 6 S.Ct. 580, 584
(1886).
[63]Emerson does not
contest that the prohibitions of the order fall within the literal terms of §
922(g)(8)(C)(ii), and the district court did not determine
otherwise.
[64]See also,
e.g.,
42 Am Jur 2d, Injunctions, § 32 at 606-08 (“To be entitled to an injunction, the
plaintiff must establish that he . . . is immediately in danger of
sustaining, some direct injury as a result of the challenged conduct. The injunction will not issue unless
there is an imminent threat of illegal action. In other words, the injury or threat
of injury must be real and immediate . . . The apprehension of injury must
be well grounded, which means there is a reasonable probability that a real
injury . . . will occur if the injunction is not granted . . .”)
(footnotes omitted; emphasis added); Id. § 8 at 566 (“The standard for
granting a preliminary injunction is essentially the same as for a permanent
injunction, with the exception that the plaintiff must show a likelihood of
success on the merits rather than actual success”) (footnote omitted).
[65]As previously observed,
see note 6, supra, the present record does not confront us with and we do
not speak to, a situation in which the defendant’s firearm possession is merely
incident to (and/or is simply passive pending initiation and completion of) a
good faith effort to rid himself, as soon after issuance of the disqualifying
court order as reasonably practicable under the circumstances, of the continued
possession of a previously possessed firearm.
[66]We reject the
special concurrence’s impassioned criticism of our reaching the issue of
whether the Second Amendment’s right to keep and bear arms is an individual
right. That precise issue was
decided by the district court and was briefed and argued by both parties in this
court and in the district court.
Moreover, in reaching that issue we have only done what the vast majority
of other courts faced with similar contentions have done (albeit our
resolution of that question is different). The vast majority have not, as
the special concurrence would have us do, simply said it makes no difference
whether or not the Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms is an individual
right because even if it were an individual right the conviction (or the
challenged statute) would be valid.
In this case, unless we were to determine the issue of the proper
construction of section 922(g)(8) in Emerson’s favor (which the special
concurrence does not suggest), resolution of this appeal requires
us to determine the constitutionality of section 922(g)(8), facially and
as applied, under the Second Amendment (as well as under the due process clause
and the commerce clause). We have
done so on a straightforward basis.
We likewise
reject the implied criticism (in the special concurrence’s fourth paragraph) for
not mentioning certain “facts” not alleged in the indictment, not found to be
true by any trier of fact, and not relevant to the section 922(g)(8) violation
alleged. The district court
dismissed the indictment and Emerson has not yet been convicted of
anything. In fact, we have been
informed that he has been acquitted of state charges relating to the
matter mentioned in the special concurrence.
[67]All pending undisposed
motions are denied.